2014 International Association for the Philosophy of Sport Natal Brazil ABSTRACTS (This is a tentative list of accepted abstracts; final abstract list will include those in attendance only) 1 Kenneth Aggerholm & Eigil Jespersen Title: Practising makes perfect Keywords: Askesis, testing, development, performance Abstract: This paper will explore a movement phenomenon that appears as a most obvious and basic part of participating in sport: practising. This phenomenon has, however, hardly received any attention in the philosophy of sport and accounts of human activity in general. There can be many reasons for this. One could be that the precise nouns and verbs that describe this phenomenon in German (Übung/üben) and Scandinavian languages (øvelse/øve, øving/øve and övning/öva) easily loose their meaning when translated into the British English noun practice or verb practise, the latter of which is practice in American English. This easily confuses the active human activity of ‘being practising’ with merely taking part in social practices. This paper will argue that it is the former that makes perfect, not the latter. Another reason for the apparent lack of interest in this phenomenon can be related to the understanding of vita activa in modern western philosophy. Arendt (1958) distinguished between three forms of activity fundamental for the human condition: labor, work and action. These can be useful to describe how activity can contribute to nurturing biological and physical fitness of the body, producing and acquiring new useful skills and crafts, and as a contrast to these, be the source of diversity, spontaneity and playfulness. But at the same time they are incapable of grasping essential aspects of human activity in what Sloterdijk calls vita performativa where we can find the practising mode of life. This points to a kind of sporting activity, where pursuing perfection need not rest on necessity (labor), involve instrumental activity (work) or merely be a disclosure of human plurality (action). To clarify the phenomenon of practising this paper will draw on Sloterdijk’s anthropology of practising, Foucault’s philosophical clarification of , and Kretchmar’s philosophical reflections on ‘testing’ in sport. From this we will highlight the most essential aspects of practising, in particular agency, effort, repetition, verticality, apprenticeship, uncertainty and self-perfection. We will present this understanding of practising as a constructive account of human activity in sport that carry both a descriptive and normative value. It can help reveal and describe a layer of meaning that can make it possible to understand the passionate engagement of athletes, distinct from instrumental qualities of performance and external motivations. This can inform a development perspective that can take sporting activity and talent development in direction of more meaningful and sustainable approaches. References Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press Foucault, Michel. 2005. The Hermeneutics of the Subject. Lectures at the Collège de France 1981-1982. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Kretchmar, R. Scott. 1975. “From test to contest: An analysis of two kinds of counterpoints in sport.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 2(1): 23–30. Sloterdijk, Peter. 2009. Du mußt dein Leben ändern. Berlin: Suhrkamp Professional and Contact Information Kenneth Aggerholm- Postdoc Institute of Sports Science and Clinical Biomechanics University of Southern Denmark Eijil Jespersen - Associate Professor Institute of Sports Science and Clinical Biomechanics University of Southern Denmark 2 [email protected] [email protected] 3 Wivi Anderson and Sigmund Loland Title: Sport and the Obligation of Solidarity Abstract: Modern sport is often linked to humanistic ideals. This is perhaps most clearly expressed in the official ideology of the Olympic Games, Olympism. In §4 of The Fundamental Principles of the IOC it is stated that the practice of sport is a human right and that sport practiced in the spirit of Olympism implies a spirit of mutual understanding, fair play and solidarity. Analyzing the case of Michelle Dumaresq, a female, transgendered downhill mountain biker whose inclusion in the female category was challenged by her competitors, we seek to examine on what conditions and in what way sport can be a sphere for solidarity. Axel Honneth’s theory of recognition (1995) provides an analytic framework. For Honneth, recognition is a fundamental need and a condition for freedom, self-realization and for establishing and maintaining a just society. According to Honneth, a democratic and just society offers recognition on three different levels to its members; love in our close relationships, rights as equal members of society, and solidarity in the civil society. The three forms of recognition constitute a reciprocal relationship to other persons or to a community, and they are also conditions for developing a sound relationship to self. Cases of disrespect, violation or marginalization that instigate moral discussion in society can be viewed a ‘struggle for recognition’ (Honneth 1995), and these moral struggles are necessary to identify unrealized moral potential. In the case of Dumaresq, her right to practice sport was protected by Canadian law and by the rules of Canadian sport. These laws and rules also secured her inclusion in downhill mountain biking as a woman. In other words, the issue at stake is not one of formal rights but one of accept and inclusion among peers; one of solidarity. With the case of Dumaresq as a background we will examine more closely sex classification in sport and how classification systems seem to be preconditions for solidarity (or the lack of it). We will argue that sport has a significant potential for solidarity, and demonstrate how Honneth’s concept of solidarity fits in with notions of fair play and fair classification. Key word: Solidarity, Honneth, transgender, classification in sport References: Teetzel, Sarah (2013) The Onus of Inclusivity: Sports Policies and the Enforcement of the Women’s Category in Sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sports, 41, 113-127 Sailor, Pam (2013) Mixed Competition and Mixed Messages. Journal of the Philosophy of Sports, 41, 6577 Hämäläinen, Mika (2013) Sport with Untapped Potential to Empower Women. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 41, 53-63. Professional and Contact Information Wivi Andersen Phd-student Norwegian School of Sport Sciences [email protected] Sigmund Loland Professor/rector Norwegian School of Sport Sciences [email protected] 4 Marco Antonio Azevedo Title: Doping, sports and the preservation of the integrity of the game Key Words: Doping, enhancements, Bernard Suits, concept of game, integrity of games. Abstract: It is well known that athletes sometimes use performance-enhancing drugs. When they are caught, such practices are severely punished by international committees. But if doping is so endemic, why not regulate rather than ban it? After all, some forms of doping are not more harmful to athletes than the practice of their sports. So, assuming that safe enhancements are possible, would still there be good arguments against its use in sports? One general complaint is that its use would compromise the athletic ideal of olympism. Olympism seems to be a set of requirements that presupposes other moral ideas, like friendship, solidarity and fair play (Parry 2006). But why the use of performance drugs would compromise olympism? After all, in using them athletes strive to be better; it is not clear why this would compromise the olympic spirit. A more specific complaint against the use of performance drugs in sports is the argument from cheating. The standard version claims that competition is only ethical if it is fair; so the rules must treat all competitors equally, and they must be luminous. Nevertheless, if fairness and luminosity were the only basic general rules against doping, then Savulescu, Foddy & Clayton (2004) are right. Drugs are against the rules; but we stipulate the rules of sport. If we made drugs legal and freely available, there would be no cheating. And if it is the welfare of the athlete that is our primary concern, drugs that do not expose athletes to excessive risks should be allowed. Vorstenbosch claims that doping harms the reasonable reciprocal expectations raised by athletes and institutional authorities (Vorstenbosch 2010). But this does not imply any categorical rule against doping. A better objection against Savulescu, Foddy & Clayton's argument is that restriction on bodily abilities is part of the rules that constitute the game. Games are played with equal artificial restrictions to all competitors, and some restrictions are constitutive parts of the game applied to all competitors equally just because they constitute the game they are all playing. Games have designed artificial obstacles whose purpose is just to create the possibility of some particular game (Suits 1978). To play a game is “to attempt to achieve a specific state of affairs, using only means permitted by rules, where the rules prohibit use of more efficient in favor of less efficient means [those are the constitutive rules of the game], and where the rules are accepted just because they make possible such activity" (Suits 1978, 41). Enhancements, hence, can be forbidden if they go against the constitutive rules of the game. If some participant has some significant inherent advantage over all the other competitors in surpassing the constitutive obstacles of a game, this form of participation disarranges the constitutive arrangement that makes a game the same for all players. By the same token, athletes with significantly different inherent advantages cannot compete in the same category. Hence, the ban of doping is related to the categorical requirement of preserving the integrity of the game. Nevertheless, to say that this requirement is categorical is not to say that it is absolute, neither moralist. It depends on the characteristics of the game, on its constitutive rules, on the kind of advantage in question, and on the required standards that make the game possible as one specific game. So, safe enhancements can be eventually permitted, provided they are open to all and do not open the case for the disfiguration of the integrity of the game. Referenecs: Savulescu, J., B. Foddy, & B. Clayton. 2004. Why we should allow performance enhancing drugs in sport. British Journal of Sports Medicine 38: 666–670. Vorstenbosch, Jan. 2010. Doping and Cheating. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 37 (2): 166-182. Murray, T.H.; Maschke, K.J. & Wasunna, A. 2009. Performance Enhancing Technologies in Sports: Ethical, Conceptual and Scientific Issues. Johns Hopkins University Professional and Contact Information Marco Antonio Azevedo Associate Professor in Philosophy Unisinos, University of Vale do Rio dos Sinos (São Leopoldo, Brazil) [email protected] 5 Claudia Böger Title: Shared situations and intersubjectivity Keywords: Intersubjectivity, phenomenal structures, shared situation Abstract Movement is not learned when a video is passively observed. We have to bodily execute movement in order to comprehend the meaning contained in it. A necessary condition that movement contains meaning is its symbolic (Metheny 1968, Cassirer 1964, Langer 1942/1980) and structural grounding. Meaning is further available as an unconscious action-guiding structure (Böger 2006). Symbolic structures are activated only via real-world experience (Danzig/Pecher/Zeelenberg/Barsalou 2007). That means that the effect of our movement exhibits the source of the meaning (Metheny 1968). Here is the overlapping with the intersubjective action within the groups of subjects executing sport. Intersubjectivity is further considered as a complex phenomenon that can be jointly perceived and understood by several participants. Every possible relation to the self presupposes a correlated world that is used as mediating part of individual epistemic processes that, in turn, applies for the structures of role and perspective assignment (Jörissen 2000, 59 in Böger 2006). Intersubjectvity is, thus, also bound to the embodiment in sport-bodily grounded experiences concerning movement of a single person or in a group. A related research question will be further explored: to what extent are meanings (as action-guiding structures) recognizable within groups and to what extend they can be further differentiated (Barsalou 2003)? Professional and Contact Information Claudia Böger Professor for sport pedagogy Institute for sport science Universität Regensburg [email protected], 6 Alberto Carrio Sampedro Title: Equality and Personal Matters in Sport Competitions Keywords: equality, personal matters, fairness, genetics, sports competitions. Abstract: Since equality is a basic principle in Sport, the aim of the normative structure of sport competitions is to avoid any inequality between participants. This explains why the norms of these competitions discriminate on the basis of gender, age, height, weight and so on. In other words, to establish different categories in competition is thought to be the best way to ensure equal opportunities between competitors. Nevertheless, these categories could become obsolete regarding both, the current level of knowledge in genetics and its impact on athletic performance and fairness in competition. Cases like the ones of the Olympic champion Eero Mäntyranta and the world champion Caster Semenya illustrate perfectly such challenges. In this paper I will argue that despite the norms of sport competitions are developed in order to ensure the moral goals of sport, namely fairness, equality and so on –the unity of values which, according to Loland, encapsulate informal fair play-; these moral goals won’t be fully ensured unless considering genetics as well as other physical and mental traits hitherto unknown, just like what is done with the rest of personal matters. References: LOLAND, S., Fair Play in Sport. A moral norm System. London, Routledge, 2002. McNAMEE, M. J. (2006). Transhumanism, medical technology and slippery slopes. Journal of Medical Ethics, 32(9), 513–518. doi:10.1136/jme.2005.013789. OSTRANDER, E., HUSON, H., OSTRANDER, G., “Genetics of Athletic Performance”, in Annual review of genomics and human genetics, 2009 (10), pp. 407-29. Professional and Contact Information Alberto Carrio Sampedro Assistant professor. Pompeu Fabra University. Barcelona [email protected] 7 Tiffany Charlotte Boyle and Prof Jo Longhurst Title: “These Gymnasts Do Not Simply Perform Gymnastics:” Portraying Whiteness in a Case Study of Contemporary Visual Art with Gymnastic Subject Matter Keywords: Visual Arts; Whiteness; Artistic Gymnastics Abstract: Whiteness permeates Artistic Gymnastics to saturation; not only does it subsist as the status quo, but its’ privileging is constantly (re)constructed by an endless number of factors, including but not limited to: the youthful demographic of the sport; the fetishisation of specific physiques, aesthetics and fashions; the European dance traditions embedded within the ‘Code of Points;’ and the display and chalking of athletes’ skin. The enduring visual representations of the sport and its popularity were cemented in the period from 1972-76, the reign of perfection via Olga Korbut and Nadia Comăneci, which continues to act as a reference point for the sports’ audience, despite the revelations and accusations made since of the sports darker side during the era. It was at this time that the sports’ image became increasingly complex, intertwined with Cold War politics, adding an aura of coldness, discipline and yet also fragility, each astute characteristics of whiteness on a individual basis, and further perpetrating both the actual image of the sport but also its’ imagined qualities. In other words, the aesthetic of gymnastics as an aesthetic sport, became self-consciously and definitively concrete. Presently, critics and theorists have identified an ‘athletic turn’ taking place in the visual arts, but what is specific about this turn with regards to certain artists who have selected gymnastic subject-matter is the unquestioning nostalgia for the aforementioned time-period in their output. This paper will introduce the work of artists Cathy Lomax and Lucy McKenzie who have each produced works within a 10-year period referencing Korbut and Comăneci, and discuss these works in relation to Other Spaces, the ongoing project of artist Jo Longhurst, which itself appropriates historic images of Comăneci and Korbut but eschews the nostalgia of other contemporary works. Other Spaces embraces the ‘whiteness’ of discipline and perfection, posing questions of power, control, gender and agency, but highlighting the difficulties associated with any form of visual representation. The aesthetic contained within all these artworks, as visual representations of Artistic Gymnastics as opposed to representations of the sport’s own aesthetic, are at once similar and at odds with Artistic Gymnastics itself. In this dialogue between curator and artist, we will tease apart these overlaps and discrepancies, and discuss the ongoing (one-way) attraction of the artist towards the gymnast. References: Connor, S.; A Philosophy of Sport, Reaktion Books: London, 2011 Gumbrecht, H. A.; In Praise of Athletic Beauty, Harvard University Press: Cambridge, MA, 2006 Longhurst, J.; Other Spaces, Ffotogallery with Mostyn, Cornerhouse, Manchester, 2012 Sontag, S.; Fascinating Fascism in: Under the Sign of Saturn, Picador: London, 2002 Professional and Contact Information Tiffany Charlotte Boyle, Curator Department of Art History & Screen Media Birkbeck, University of London [email protected] Prof Jo Longhurst, Artist Centre for Fine Art Research Birmingham School of Art,Birmingham City University [email protected] 8 Daniel Campos Title: Sporting Creativity, Enriched Communities, and Integral Personal Education Key Words: Sport, Creativity, Education Abstract: This paper addresses the question: Why should there be philosophical interest in defining, describing, and understanding sporting creativity? Adopting a Peircean perspective, the paper will emphasize two interrelated kinds of reasons, namely, the importance of creativity (a) for enriching sporting communities and (b) for enhancing the integral education of the individual members of those communities. This paper takes as a starting point a definition of sporting creativity that is based on a phenomenological account of sporting experience. Taking philosophical cues from the thought of Charles Sanders Peirce, it posits that creativity in sporting activity is the ability to respond to the physical challenges encountered in the practice of sport in spontaneous and imaginative ways on the basis of carefully cultivated physical and mental—or bodyminded—habits. This definition involves several key Peircean notions such as imagination, spontaneity, habit, and the continuity of body and mind. They will be explained as necessary to advance the paper’s main objective; namely, to consider some reasons why sporting creativity is of philosophical interest to sporting communities and, especially, for the integral education of the bodyminded person (section I). These reasons are recast in terms of possibilities for creative self-realization in sport, highlighting the upshot of an education for creativity (section II). The first point about communities is a general feature of Peirce’s systematic thought—creative individuals can be agents for promoting the growth and enrichment of their communities, e.g. for communities of scientific inquiry to advance towards the knowledge of truth. In the case of sport, creative individuals and creative acts—in the sense of creativity as promoting effective problem-solving within the constraints and rules of the sport—enrich the practice of communities. This point is developed in relation to work by Teresa Lacerda and Stephen Mumford (2011) and Peter Hopsicker (2010) Regarding the improvement and development of the individual within the community, phenomenological attention to the processes and experience of sporting creativity holds the promise of improving the integral education of the sportsperson. This includes the sporting education of the person, but it goes beyond it. Fostering creativity in sporting activity may lead, for learners and strivers of all ages and levels, to the integral education of the bodyminded person. The meaning of “integral education” will be worked out with reference to work by William Sadler (1977) and Douglas Anderson (2001). References: Anderson, Douglas. 2001. “Recovering Humanity: Movement, Sport, and Nature.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 28: 140 – 150. Hopsicker, Peter. 2011. “In Seach of the ‘Sporting Genius’: Exploring the Benchmarks to Creative Behavior in Sporting Activity.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 38: 113-127. Lacerda, Teresa and Mumford, Stephen. 2010. “The Genius in Art and in Sport: A Contribution to the Investigation of Aesthetics of Sport.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 37: 182-193. Sadler Jr., William A. 1977. “Alienated Youth and Creative Sports’ Experience.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 4: 83 – 95. Lacerda, Teresa and Mumford, Stephen. 2010. “The Genius in Art and in Sport: A Contribution to the Investigation of Aesthetics of Sport.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 37: 182-193. Sadler Jr., William A. 1977. “Alienated Youth and Creative Sports’ Experience.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 4: 83 – 95. Professional and Contact Information Daniel G. Campos Associate Professor Department of Philosophy Brooklyn College — City University of New York [email protected] 9 Lamartine DaCosta and Paulo Rodrigo DaSilva Title: Intrinsic Values VS Ideology in Philosophy of Sport–Overview of Insights from U.S. and Brazil Key Words: Sport, ideology, values, ethics Abstract: According to DaCosta (2014) the theme of ideology remains today as a major concern from social or political philosophy, however it still attracts the interest of a few but relevant thinkers of sport mainly concentrated in North America. That is the case of John Hoberman, Allen Guttmann and William J. Morgan who keep their specificity otherwise agreeing with the opposing views of sport: one is looking in ideology-bound directions, the other into the constructive social values as opposed to dominant ideology. Point-specific, Hoberman had met this Janus-like approach in his early writings from the 1970s, suggesting that sport was “innocuous” facing the appropriation of sport by ideologybased interests. Later he joined Guttmann and Morgan in the support of the thesis of sport as a means of values-led emancipation and freedom, an insight still prevalent today. Generally speaking, since the 1960s some European and Latin American thinkers influenced by Marxism framed sport as a means of social dominance neglecting its attribute of self-realization. In Brazil, for instance, Marxist interpretation of sport became a mainstream thought among social researchers, leaving behind the intrinsic values of sport. Eventually this characteristic feature is identified nowadays as argued by Oliveira (2013) who followed the construction of knowledge in sport and Physical Education by national surveys in this particular country beginning in 1971. Thus far, this contribution aims to review the fact-findings promoted by Oliveira (2013) focusing on the presupposed Brazil-based negligence with the notion of values-driven sport. Briefly, this overview suggests that the concentration on the version of dominance is mostly an ethical claim not an explicit rejection of sport in its competitive dimension. Ipso facto the today’s distinction between U.S. and Brazil in terms of insights about the Janus-like understanding of sport is a matter of choice not a contradiction. This conclusion is compatible with the results of an empirical research conducted by Loland and Ommundsen (1996) in Norway when it was investigated the perception of the general population towards children’s sport’s values and ideology. For those philosophers of sport the latter apparent ambivalence meant a simple distinction between sport’s intrinsic values and the beliefs about sport competition cultivated by the wider society. References: DaCosta, L.P. (2014) Sport and Ideology. In Torres, C. (Ed) The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Sport. London: Bloomsbury, pp. 2012 – 227. Santana, A.F.S. (2013) Diagnosis of Sport in Brazil. Doctoral Thesis – Universidade Federal da Bahia, Salvador. Loland, S. and Ommundsen, Y. (1996) Values and Ideologies of Norwegian Children’s Sport as Perceived by the General Population. European Physical Education Review 2 (1996), 133–42. Professional and Contact Information Lamartine DaCosta Professor State University of Rio de Janeiro [email protected] Paulo Rodrigo Pedroso DaSilva PhD student, State University of Rio de Janeiro [email protected], 10 Yuval Eylon and Amir Horowitz Title: Who deserves to win in football? Key words: desert; winning; justice; luck; sporting values. Abstract: The concept of desert plays an important role in moral philosophy, in political philosophy, and in other axiological enquiries. Our purpose in this talk is to explore the application of this concept to the domain of sport, and specifically to that of football (soccer). The question as far as this domain is concerned is who deserves to win a particular game, to win a championship or a tournament, etc. There are several dimensions to this question. First, the question can be reduced to, or understood in terms of, the question of "general" moral desert, or, in other words, that of "cosmic justice". Who, in the final analysis, taken all morally relevant facts into consideration, deserves to win? Or, What score (if any) would make the world morally better? Considerations that are relevant to the question thus understood include the well-being of the relevant individuals (or teams, or nations and the like), their moral merits (based on the way they conducted their life), and so forth. These considerations have little to do with sport and sporting values, though arguably they might be weighed against such values. Let's refer to such considerations as "external". Now let's move to "internal" considerations. There is a sense in which the one who deserves to win is simply the one who plays better – the athlete or team that better exercises the abilities relevant to the game. It is possible to think that (assuming no erroneous decisions on the part of the referee are involved) this is simply the one who does win, but as we have shown in a previous work, this isn't necessarily so, especially with respect to football. You can demonstrate the relevant abilities better than your opponent yet lose the game. It is due to luck that abilities and success in football can come apart. Who deserves to win when winning and playing better do come apart? And does the team that plays better (and even wins) always deserve to win? Finally, how are all these notions of desert related to the concept of desert having to do with cosmic justice? We will explore this conceptual space and try to answer these questions. In so doing, we will also discuss the related issue of the relations between the concepts of fair behavior in general on the one hand, and the concept of fair play and thick concepts of sporting values such as those of daring and determination on the other hand. Referenecs: Kagan, Shelly. The Geometry of Desert, Oxford University Press, 2012. Pojman and McLeod, eds., What Do We Deserve? Oxford University Press, 1998. Simmons, Robert, "Deserving to Be Lucky: Reflections on the Role of Luck and Desert in Sport", Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 34 (2007, 13-25. Professional and Contact Information Yuval Eylon Senior Lecturer in Philosophy The Open University of Israel [email protected] Amir Horowitz Associate Professor of Philosophy The Open University of Israel [email protected] 11 Jeffrey Fry Title: “What was it Like to be Like Mike? Or, My Absent Qualia? Key Words: qualia, consciousness, what’s it like? Abstract: In his widely-cited piece entitled “What is it Like to be a Bat?,” the philosopher Thomas Nagel states the following: “But fundamentally an organism has conscious mental states if and only if there is something that it is like to be that organism—something it is like for the organism.” He adds: “We may call this the subjective character of experience.” 1 In this paper I contemplate what it might have been like to be an elite athlete like Michael Jordan at the height of his athletic prowess. On the one hand, according to Nagel, we cannot know what it is like to be a bat. Its form of existence is alien to us. On the other hand, Nagel thinks that we can, based on our own experiences, approximate an understanding of what it is like to be another person. But what about knowing what it was like to be an elite athlete such as Michael Jordan? The television commercials encouraged us to “Be Like Mike,” and in Walter Mitty-like excursions through imaginative space, I can picture myself soaring from the free throw line to slam home a dunk shot. But can I really ever know what it was like to be like Michael Jordan? In part this is the question of qualia. Do they exist, and if so, what is their nature? According to some familiar arguments, no amount of pouring over Jordan’s statistics will tell me what it was like to be like Mike, in the sense of what his qualia were like. No account of the physical facts pertaining to his anatomy or physiology will do the job. Can anyone tell me? Perhaps LeBron James? Can I know it by introspection? Can even Michael Jordan at this point know what it was like to be Michael Jordan? Are his memories faithful memories? Perhaps what it was like to be like Mike has been lost in the mist of time. This line of questioning presupposes that there was something that it was like to be like Mike? But is that true? Do my experiences lack qualia that Michael Jordan experienced? What about the possibility of zombie-Michael Jordan? I argue that these issues point to the bigger issue of what it means to be a human being, and that significant ethical implications follow from the responses to these issues about the nature of consciousness. References: (1) David J. Chalmers. “Facing up to the Problem of Consciousness,” in Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology, edited by John Heil, 617-640. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. (2) Thomas Nagel. “What is it Like to be a Bat?”, in Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology, edited by John Heil, 528-538. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. (3) Edmond Wright, editor. The Case for Qualia. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2008. Professional and Contact Information Associate Professor Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies Ball State University [email protected] 1 Thomas Nagel, “What is it Like to be a Bat?”, in Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology, edited by John Heil, 528-538. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. The quotation is found on p. 529. 12 Koyo Fukasawa and Ai Aramaki Title: Beyond the border and changing public attitudes: Olympic education as intangible legacy Key Words: Cosmopolitanism, educational aim, moral value, publics Abstract: The International Olympic Committee (IOC) added the term ‘Legacy’ to the Olympic Charter in 2003. Legacy is the notion of focusing on sustainable urban development seen over the long term rather than shortterm economic benefits. The IOC is attempting to create a system to make the relationship between sports and society a reality through the Olympic Games by increasing the awareness toward environmental issues for future generations. There are two types of Olympic Legacy, tangible and intangible. The intangible legacy is, especially, difficult to be recognized and measured, however it is more important. It may have a direct or an indirect impact on society. We should approach this intangible legacy, which is understood as a temporal event, with future generation in mind. Olympic education is one of the key approaches to make clear this intangible legacy, since it is focused on future generations. Therefore, this essay aims at considering what educational goals should be pursued in Olympic education. According to Naul (2008), Olympic education has focused on a set of social virtues and moral values applied within sport activities and in the setting of children and young people since the 2000s. How should we recognize such virtues and ethical values? Coubertin, who already had a basic philosophy of cosmopolitanism, suggested that we should aim to introduce a temporary truce into differences. Accordingly, we should iron out cultural distinctions, values, and systems so as to transcend the framework of nationality. His ideal, however, has not been fully realized yet.(Morgan, 1995) Because sports and games include confrontational element and events, we need to discuss how solidarity can be introduced through competitive scenarios and into people who have different cultural values. The idea of cosmopolitanism by Kant(1785) is more realistic and convincing in regard to this point. Public attitude is important for cosmopolitanism: it is an attitude that should be encouraged; it is an attitude that aims at making use of one’s reason publicly. According to Kant(1784), this means not thinking about how to benefit one’s own country or local government (since this entails the private use of reason). Rather, this means using reason as a scholar with the public’s common good in mind. One must be free for that. Accordingly, to adopt this attitude, it is necessary to bracket one’s own benefit. Regarding solidarity, we should explore both possibilities, that of going beyond national borders, and that of overcoming generational barriers. Concerning the former, the spirit of fairness and rule following should be valued. As far as the latter, it will require to see future generations as ‘the other’ which involves considering the self as the other at the same time. Because this ensures freedoms for people and contributes to development of the Olympic movement without being affected by nation-states. In this way, to learn to bracket the differences from others should be set as a goal of Olympic education rather than ironing out differences. References Kant, I. [trans. Daniel Fidel Ferrer] (1784 [2013]) Answer the question: What is enlightenment? (https://archive.org/stream/AnswerTheQuestionWhatIsEnlightenment/KantEnlightmentDanielFidelFerrer20 13#page/n0/mode/2up) Kant, I. [trans. Campbell Smith] (1785 [1903]) Perpetual Peace. (https://archive.org/stream/perpetualpeacea00kantgoog#page/n124/mode/2up) William J. Morgan (1995) Cosmopolitanism, Olympism, and Nationalism. Olympika, 4, pp. 79-92 Roland Naul (2008) Olympic Education, Oxford: Meyer and Meyer:UK, p.13. Professional and Contact Information Koyo Fukasawa Ai Aramaki Associate Professor Ph.D candidate University of Tsukuba University of Tsukuba [email protected] [email protected] 13 Paul Gaffney Title: Moral Victories Key Words: competition, psychology, development Abstract: A “moral victory” seems to be something of a paradox. It suggests that something positive has occurred or has been achieved although the result was—as a matter of fact—a defeat. The qualifier ‘moral’ thus serves to qualify or even override the factual outcome. And yet the fact remains. Competitive sport is not entirely a matter of moral evaluation or else there would be no paradox or qualification involved in the term: we would simply say that the player or the team played well, courageously, nobly, etc., and leave it at that. But we do not because, however important those qualities are, in the context of competitive sport they find their intelligibility in the factual outcomes of the event. Moral victories thus stand as a rebuke to strict zero-sum logic, and yet presuppose it on some level. It is possible to play well and lose, just as it is possible to play poorly and win. Although the latter can shake a player’s confidence or rhythm, we do not typically speak of “moral defeats,” possibly because the successful outcome somehow mitigates the poor showing. In other words, there seems not to be a perfect symmetry here, which complicates our understanding of the relationship between winning and losing and how one wins or loses. The invocation of a moral victory seems to presume a long-term as opposed to a short-term or an “event” vantage point. That is, we understand that this particular competitive event might go down in the loss column, but that is not the only way to consider the efforts and the achievements of the competitors. Very often moral victories are part of a player’s (or a team’s) natural development, which comes with the implicit suggestion that this performance is one to build on for the future. But the developmental understanding is not the only species of moral victory: a veteran player or team at the end of a career can achieve a moral victory in contest with a stronger opponent. Generally speaking, anytime an overmatched opponent performs honorably and courageously and—it must ultimately come down to this—competitively, there is an occasion for a moral victory. The developmental understanding is of particular interest because it comes with an implicit promise that one day this moral victory will turn into a real victory. In other words, it would seem that a moral victory can only provide limited solace and encouragement, which is why we sometimes hear coaches or players say things like, “We are past the point of moral victories.” A competitor who only had moral victories to show for his or her career might possibly—and perhaps unfairly—develop a reputation for not being able to win the big one. The psychology of moral victories is also an interesting investigation because it would seem that whatever satisfaction a moral victory provides, it can be neither directly pursued nor fully enjoyed. References: Carr, D. (1999). Where’s the merit if the best man wins? Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 26: 1-9. Dixon, N. (1999). On winning and athletic superiority. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 26: 10-26 Kretchmar, R.S. (2013). Competition, redemption, and hope. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport. 39: 101-116 Professional and Contact Information Paul Gaffney Chair and Associate Professor of Philosophy St. John’s University, NY [email protected] 14 John Gleaves and Tim Lehrbach Title: Beyond Fairness: Rethinking Gender’s Role in Sport in Light of Trans* and Intersex Athletes and Mixed-Gender Competitions Keywords: Gender, Transgender, Intersex, Fairness Abstract: Scholars have long recognized sport as a vehicle for establishing and expressing visions of masculinity and femininity. This includes transgender or transsexual (trans*) and intersex athletes. Because such individuals have a moral entitlement to sport, fears about exclusion, perceptions of hostility towards gender non-conforming athletes, or actual rules that bar participants from competing have garnered attention among scholars. Many scholars have attacked any exclusion of athletes on the grounds that they do not upset the equality of conditions among the athletes. This focus on “equality amongst competitors” has provided some leverage against efforts to exclude such athletes from sport. However, while we agree with sentiments towards inclusivity, the arguments that hinge on equality among competitors are philosophically unsatisfying. We will argue that fairness is not the issue that should determine inclusion; rather, the issue is ensuring that the value assigned to gendered meaning in sporting contests does not outweigh other significant values associated with sport. In this paper, we will first historicize notions of equality in sport and show that rather than being the “gold standard” of idealized sport, they are a modern invention that can enhance certain aspects of sport, such as comparative outcomes and competitive enjoyment. We will then argue that such aspects are only part of the value of sport and must be considered balanced with other aspects of sport, such as lusory enjoyment or personal narrative. With this holistic notion of sport’s values, we argue that gendered narratives must also be considered as a component of good sport but that their role may be overvalued and ought to be reduced so that they balance with other desired aspects of sport. We will assert that at youth levels, such gendered narratives make little sense while at gradually higher levels of elite sport the desire for equal conditions or gendered narratives is less important than inclusions and participation. Last, we will argue that even at the highest levels of sport, the plurality of gender expression can fit with athletes self-selecting their participation gender when a sport requires gendered competition and competing in mixed gender competitions when such requirements are unnecessary. We conclude that sport should greatly reduce its desire to enforce cisgenderded binary sport and work to create sporting climates that show equal concern for sport’s valued qualities. This would involve increased gender neutral competitions, cessation of sex testing, and permission for athletes to self-select their gender category. References: Schultz, J. (2011). Caster Semenya and the "Question of Too": Sex Testing in Elite Women's Sport and the Issue of Advantage. Quest, 63(2), 228-243. Sykes, H. (2006). Transsexual and Transgender Policies in Sport. Women in Sports and Physical Acitivity Journal, 15(1), 3-13. Teetzel, S. (2006). On Transgendered Athletes, Fairness and Doping: An International Challenge. Sport in Society: Cultures, Commerce, Media, Politics, 9(2), 227-251. Professional and Contact Information John Gleaves California State University, Fullerton [email protected] Tim Lehrbach Independent Scholar [email protected] 15 Mika Hämäläinen Title: Hitler, Jesse Owens and a Finnish Sprinter Keywords: athletic superiority, anti-Semitism, sport Abstract: Imagine that Hitler would have had the power to control the official results of the 1936 Berlin Olympics. Next, imagine that he would have nullified the results of Jesse Owens, an African American athlete, who achieved four gold medals in the Games. The idea is repelling. We may, however, face a similar situation even without using our imagination. In 1938, Jewish Abraham Tokazier participated in a 100-metre race at Helsinki Olympic Stadium in Finland. He crossed the finish line first according to a photograph taken by a spectator. Nevertheless, Tokazier was officially declared as being fourth. Helsingin Sanomat, a Finnish newspaper, wrote on the next day that goal judges had made a coarse error. The newspaper contended that Tokazier had won and portrayed the picture in which Tokazier crosses the finish line first. However, there is an additional explanation for the unexpected official results. They may have been an anti-Semitic action that was intended to please National Socialistic German spectators. In 2013, the Finnish Amateur Athletic Association overturned the original results and declared Tokazier as a winner. This happened 75 years after the competition and 37 years after Tokazier’s death. Tokazier’s case poses two intriguing philosophical issues. The first issue concerns the alteration of official results: Should the official results be changed in some cases afterwards, and if they should, what principle should guide the alteration? These questions are also relevant for doping issues. Second, we can ask whether Tokazier was the best athlete of the 1938 contest not until the official results were altered or was he best independently of the official results. I will focus on the latter issue by analysing the case through three different standards of athletic superiority. However, the focus of my paper does not amount to ignoring the first issue, since the two issues are interconnected. In other words, by addressing the latter issue we can achieve better insight into the former. References: Dixon, Nicholas 1999. On Winning and Athletic Superiority. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 26, 10– 26. Loland, Sigmund 2002. Fair Play in Sport. A moral norm system. London and New York: Routledge. Suits, Bernard 2010. Construction of a Definition. In The Ethics of Sports. A Reader, edited by Mike McNamee 17–28. London and New York: Routledge. Professional and Contact Information Mika Hämäläinen Doctoral candidate University of Turku [email protected], 16 Peter Hopsicker Title: The Value of Perfection: A Critical Examination of the Asymptotic in Sporting Behavior Key Words: Perfection, Polanyi, Asymptote Abstract: Plato once wrote, “In order for man to succeed in life, God provided him with two means, education and physical activity. Not separately, one for the soul and the other for the body, but for the two together. With these two means, man can attain perfection.”In modern times, we continue to seek human “perfection,” to seek the limits of our physical and intellectual abilities. Recent books by Gladwell (Outliers, 2008; David and Goliath, 2013), Colvin (Talent is Overrated, 2008), Coyle (The Talent Code, 2009), Syed (Bounce, 2010), Epstein (The Sports Gene, 2013), and Kotler (The Rise of Superman, 2014) attempt to unlock the secrets of talent development in multiple practices, including sport, to elite and world-class levels. Referencing scientific data and case studies, these works search for the formula, which includes components originating from both nature and nurture that could suggest pathways leading to extraordinary human performance. At the same time, Sandel (The Case Against Perfection, 2007) and Brown (“The Case for Perfection,” JPS, 2009) debate the propriety of circumventing the “genetic lottery” through the means of biotechnology and other performance enhancements. At least one of the ends projected in these works is superior human performance. Additionally, books by Brenkus (The Perfection Point, 2010) and Borrow (Mathletics, 2012) specifically look into the biomechanical science behind the limitations of human movement and even go so far as to predict the absolute limits of human performance—the asymptote where, largely due to the physiological limitations of the flesh, humans can approach but never exceed in terms of speeds, heights, distances and times. The “perfection point,” as Brenkus calls it, refers to “points we can edge closer to yet never surpass.” This recent surge of interest in “perfection” highlights humankind’s continuing fascination with developing pathways to the “perfect” human and, furthermore, the concurrent discussion of “nature’s” and/or “nurture’s” contribution to such ends. However, this body of literature does not come to a consensus on what should be considered “perfect” in the context of motor performance in sport. Is it a function of limitations in the physical matter of the human body, such as the 8.99 seconds in the 100-meter sprint suggested by Brenkus? Is it the point of “ultimate human performance,” as Kotler describes it, where any mistake in performance can result in major injury or even death? Or is it an abstract concept of the mind, such as the sprinter’s mentality that, with enough dedication, practice, and effort, he/she will someday achieve a time of 0:00:00? Perhaps more importantly, these works only thinly address the value of striving or even reaching such points to sport and motor performance practices. In this paper, I will use the ideas of Michael Polanyi to reframe this discussion. First, I will briefly introduce Polanyi’s conception of evolution as “a human feat of emergence.” I will then delineate his conception of “perfection” as an “imaginative projection.” Finally, I will use his conception of “moral inversion” to provide direction for future research on human potential. Conclusions will suggest the value of striving and achieving “perfection” in sport and physical activity practices. References: Brenkus, J. 2010. The perfection point. New York: Harper-Collins Publishers. Epstein, D. 2013. The sports gene. New York: Current. Polanyi, M. and Prosch, H. 1975. Meaning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Professional and Contact Information Peter Hopsicker Associate Professor of Kinesiology Penn State Altoona [email protected] 17 Daniel Hutto Conference Keynote Address Title: Which Embodied Cognition Should Inform Sports Science? A Philosophical Decider Abstract: The sciences of mind have taken a decisively embodied turn. The fact that the mind is embodied in important and surprising ways is now beyond serious dispute. Scientists (e.g. Beilock 2008) are calling for sports science to be informed by the embodied cognition framework. Yet different frameworks for understanding embodied cognition have emerged, which can be classified in terms of the degree to which they retain the notion of mental representations in their accounts. At one end of the spectrum are ultra-conservative accounts (see, e.g., Goldman 2012). At the other end are radical replacement accounts that see no role for mental representations in our best theories of mind (Hutto and Myin 2013). This paper provides (1) philosophical reasons for preferring radical embodied theories over the conservative sort, and (2) explicates how a radical take on embodied and enactive cognitive science might inform sports science. Biosketch Daniel D. Hutto is Professor of Philosophical Psychology at the University of Wollongong (Australia) and the University of Hertfordshire(UK). His most recent books include: Wittgenstein and the End of Philosophy (Palgrave, 2006), Folk\ Psychological Narratives (MIT, 2008) and is co‐author of Radicalizing Enactivism (MIT, 2013). He was a chief co-investigator for the Australian Research Council ‘Embodied Virtues and Expertise’ project (2010-2013). He is a node leader in the Marie Curie Action 'Towards an Embodied Science of Intersubjectivity’ Initial training network (2011-2015) and a collaborator of the 'Agency, Normativity and Identity' project (2012-2015) funded by the Spanish Ministry of Innovation and Research. 18 Jung Hyun Hwang Title: Justice in Distributions by Desert in Sport: Aristotelian Practical Perspectives Key words: distribution, justice, Aristotle, desert, sport Abstract: In this paper I will analyze what “distributive justice” means in sport. It refers to the reward accompanying the result of a game which are factors of strong motivation. They are the pleasure of gain and deriving excellent performance. All who gets awards for meritorious deeds in sporting competitions with physical or mental exertion, even moral accountability have no doubts about differential treatment between competitors. The extra amount of sweat that winners exert doesn’t amount to discrimination between winners and losers. It raises important questions about the warrant for identifying justice of distribution. Please think about, why winners get more profit than other players? I will use the analyses of distributive justice in sport by Aristotle to examine it. I will argue, therefore, that Aristotle emphasized the principle of distribution from human agency. It is excellence from Nichomachean Ethics and Politics. The excellence, namely arête, is related to desert. We may have regarded winners as superior players to any other players. Even though they get more rewards such as fame, popularity, honor, even prize money because their desert as winners has been more respected. Aristotle (NE, 1131a25-28) argues that the principle of assignment by desert that is justice in distributions must be based on desert of some sort. However, I will focus on the connection of excellence and desert to explain justice in distribution by referring to Aristotle’s theory, “flute analogy” in Politics (1282b14-1283a3). As Aristotle says that the superior performer in playing the flute has the grounds for possessing flute. Yet if this is true, the main reason to receive the flute is because of the greater good ability to play the flute. The talent or ability to play flute contributes in distribution. According to Aristotle, it is a fair distribution based on excellence. We have found that athlete’s excellence has connection with desert. The champion or gold medal laureate can get more prize money, fame, honor and etc. We have understood that winners have precisely better skills than others so that there is no reason that they should receive more merit. It is the justice way of distribution in Aristotle’s theory. Here, we need to focus on excellence which is a virtue of human agency. But, it requires two conditions, appropriateness and dessert. For example, a marathoner and sprinter need different types of excellence to do a good performance. Suppose, a marathoner has physical size, conditioned muscle mass like sprinter, the marathoner may find it difficult to do an excellent performance. In this case, the physical conditions for marathoner and its desert are not suited for excellence. I expect that this research reframes what justice is. By dividing reward in sport is desert. This analysis requires three steps. Firstly, we concentrate on Aristotle’s theory of distributive justice through his works, Nichomachean Ethics and Politics. Secondly, we focus on practical distribution in reality in sport. Lastly, we can understand the player’s excellence and justice in a different distribution. Professional and Contact Information Jung Hyun Hwang Assistant Professor Wonkwang University, Korea [email protected] 19 Jesus Illundain and Kevin Krein Title: Sport’s Flow and Martial Art’s Mushin: A Dynamic, Historical, and Generative Phenomenological Analysis Key Words: Mushin, flow, phenomenology, Husserl, Ortega Abstract: In “Mushin and Flow: An East-West Comparative Analysis,” its authors conclude, “Even if it were assumed that the two phenomena begin with the “same” raw sensations, when they are filtered through Japanese culture, and martial arts conducted under the aegis of a do, the two will differ phenomenologically” (in Priest and Young 2014). They further claim that while the phenomena are analogous, given the different cultural context, the two will “in the long run, acquire different qualitative properties” (ibid). Nonetheless, their account is thin in terms of actual phenomenological description of said qualities and specification of how culture affects these. This presentation expands on their promissory and promising comparison. The project stays close to the facts of sporting and martial experience. Specifically, it adapts kinesthetic (Sheets-Johnstone 2011) and existential (Breivik 2011) phenomenological analyses of movement to draw an East-West comparative examination of sports and martial arts that highlights common and disparate qualitative dynamics. Unprecedentedly, it supplements these with a joint and contrasted historical (Ortega 1962) and Husserlian generative (Steinbock 1995) phenomenological examination. This shows the radically constitutive role that history, culture, intersubjectivity, normativity, geography, weather, and other variables have on the way flow and mushin states are interpreted and felt. In other words, Orteguian historical reason and Husserlian generation disclose novel and enriching descriptions and interpretations of the aforementioned dynamics such that these are tied to their geo-historical development. Auspiciously, this shows the applicability and vets the validity of the diverse phenomenologies engaged and, more pertinently for our purposes, affords a richer understanding of sporting flow and martial mushin. References: Breivik, Gunnar (2011). Dangerous Play with the Elements: Towards a phenomenology of Risk Sports. Sports, Ethics and Philosophy. 5(3), 314-330. Jackson S. and Csikszentmihalyi, M. 1999. Flow in Sports. Champaign: Human Kinetics. Krein K. and Ilundáin-Agurruza, J. 2014. “An East-West Comparative Analysis of Mushin and Flow.” Philosophy and the Martial Arts. Priest G. & Young D. (eds.). London: Routledge. Ortega y Gasset, J. 1962. History as a System and Other Essays Toward a Philosophy of History. New York & London: W.W. Norton and Co. Sheets-Johsntone, M. 2011. The Primacy of Movement. 2nd Ed. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing. Co. Steinbock, A.J. 1995. Home and Beyond: Generative Phenomenology after Husserl. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Suzuki, D.T. 1993. Zen in Japanese Culture. New York: Princeton University Press. Takuan Soho. 1987. The Unfettered Mind. Trans. W. S. Wilson, Tokyo. Kodansha International. Yagyu, Munenori. 2003. The Life Giving Sword. Trans. W.S. Wilson. Tokyo: Kodansha International. Professional and Contact Information Jesus Illundain Associate Professor of Philosophy Linfield College, USA [email protected] Kevin Krein Assoc. Professor of Philosophy University of Alaska Southeast, Juneau, AK 99801 [email protected] 20 Ivo Jirásek, Title: Vastness as the specific category of trans-ocean sailing Key Words: Trans-ocean sailing, spirituality, travelling, vastness, non-religious pilgrimage Abstract: Long-distance sailing as a kind of travelling is not ordinary tourism, but rather can be characterized according to certain specific features of non-religious pilgrimage. Characteristic and value of sailing experience was studied (Allison at al., 2007), however, the ontological quality (as vastness) is missing in existing research. The goal our study is prove the vastness category as a specific ontological and anthropological characteristic of trans-ocean sailing, in fact on an actual journey from New Zealand to the Falkland Islands around Cape Horn. This paper will analyze the diary of a participant on board the Dutch ship Oosterschelde and use hermeneutic method for deeper understanding of such experience. Vastness is declared as a specific category of trans-ocean sailing which support also understanding of such travelling in framework of non-religious pilgrimage. Some journeys and travelling, like trans-ocean sailing, should be perceived in a framework of nonreligious spirituality among others thanks to vastness category. Personal and Contact Information Ivo Jirásek Professor Faculty of Physical Culture, Palacký University Olomouc Czech Republic [email protected] 21 Lev Kreft Title: Antiocularcentrism and Sport Spectacle Keywords: sport spectacle, antiocularcentrism, new media, everyday life, critique Abstract: The starting point of this paper is Martin Jay's extensive study Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century French Thought (Jay,1993). Suspicion, criticism and attack on watching, seeing, looking and any other way of enjoyment of vision, is exemplified by French thought, but it is present well beyond French culture, where it includes, beside Bergson, Bataille, Breton, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Lacan, Althusser, Barthes, Levinas, Lyotard and Derrida also »Foucault's strictures against the medical gaze and panoptic surveilleance«, and »Debord's critique of the society of the spectacle« (Jay, 1993, 588). This »profound suspicion of vision and its hegemonic role in the modern era« (Jay, 1993, 14) occupies a prominent place in most discourses on sport spectacles, after their core public does not consist any more of those present at the site, but from those who watch new media images, and are able to do so from any point of the globe and at any time, from innumerable virtual resources obtainable through more and more numerous means of digital technology products. In fact, criticism of sport spectatorship has spread so widely that it represents a discipline of its own, where panopticum's surveillance applies together with general assessment that ours is a society of the spectacle – which means that sport's massive global public has lost its touch with the real, and succumbed to alienation, manipulation and ideology. Spectacle, and consequently sport spectacle, together with huge global public created by such unprecedented accessibility does not cease to attract criticism which states that thanks to the global system of new media spectacles sport has become what religion used to be: a false transcendence of human otherwise banal everyday life. In this paper, I will first offer an overview of the critique of spectacle and of the sport spectacle with a special focus on radical critique of sport by Jean-Marie Brohm (Brohm, 2006). Then, I will propose another approach to philosophy of the spectacle, starting from Michel de Certeau’s The Practice of Everyday Life (Certeau, 1988) and from Ágnes Heller’s philosophy of the radical criticism, and of the everyday life (Heller, 1984). Without ambition to develop a complete representation of their views, I will dwell upon what they have in common, namely, that even under circumstances of modern anonymous masses and means of spectacularization, one should never treat people as passive and unconscious object of given circumstances. General contradiction of all critiques of sport spectacle is that they start from enlightenment’s position of criticism, but arrive at anti-enlightenment patronizing of sport spectacle’s public. Finally, I will defend sport spectacle, in spite of its alienating, manipulative and ideological effects attacked by antiocularcentrist critique, as plebeian entrance into global world and its fascinations, which, after a long period of criticism, needs at least some philosophical understanding. References: Brohm, J.-M. 2006. La Tyrannie sportive - Théor e cr t que d’un op um du people. Paris: Beauchesne. Certeau, Michel de. 1988. The Practice of Everyday Life (transl. by S. Rendall). Berkeley-Los Angeles-London: University of California Press. Heller, Á. 1984. Everyday Life (transl. by G.L. Campbell). London: Routledge and Keegan Paul. Jay, M. 1993. Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth Century French Thought. Berkeley-Los Angeles-London: University of California Press. Professional and Contact Information Leve Kreft Prof. of Aesthetics, Faculty of Arts University of Ljubljana [email protected] 22 R. Scott Kretchmar Title: Multiple Game Structures: An Addendum to ‘Game Flaws’ Abstract: In previous discussions (Kretchmar, 2005), I identified two species of games that manage game duration in very different ways—those that specify a number of tests that have to be negotiated prior to completion (event regulated) and those that allot a period of time during which testing can occur (time regulated). Golf and baseball are examples of the former wherein 18 holes or 27 outs, respectively, must be negotiated under normal circumstances before the game is over. Basketball and soccer are examples of the latter method for regulating testing duration. A set amount of time is permitted (usually divided into halves or other temporal segments) for testing and contesting. The game is over when time runs out. The upshot of this research was that these two versions of games carry distinctive assets and liabilities. While I described both structures as functional, I argued that the event regulated design is normatively superior and that most games today are built in this way. I believe this analysis is still sound as far as it goes, but I now realize it did not go far enough. It overlooked a third variety of game, one that I will identify as “achievement regulated.” This species of game is over if and when a specified goal is reached. This is the kind of game identified by Suits in his discussion of lusory goals, his analysis of games like chess, and his description of “games without rules” and the scaling of Mt. Impossible. I will make and defend a number of claims related to this third type of game. First, I will speculate on its relationship to the other two varieties of games. I will identify achievement-regulated as the most primitive form of gaming (among the three) for several reasons including, but not limited to, its lesser or non-dependence on constitutive rules, its more central focus on the lusory attitude, the likelihood that games of this sort were among the first played by our ancestors, difficulties inherent in choosing “just right” achievements in contrast to just right hurdles, and uncertainties related to game duration. I will summarize its advantages and disadvantages in relationship to time and event regulated contests. The full analysis will also include a discussion of hybrid games that employ more than one of these strategies for determining test duration. Finally, the address will include a postscript on Suits’ confused analysis of the different ends, goals, and purposes of games and their relationship to the issue of game duration. References: Kretchmar, S. (2005). Game flaws. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, XXXII, 36-48. Suits, B. (2005). The grasshopper: Games, life and utopia. (Introduction by Thomas Hurka). Toronto: Broadview Press. Professional and Contact Information R. Scott Kretchmar Professor Penn State University [email protected] 23 Teresa Lacerda Conference Keynote Address Title: “Transcendence – An Aesthetic Category that Outlines the Aesthetic Value of Sport” Abstract: Although aesthetics of sport is broadly taken in account in certain academic circles it is still quite absent from other sport contexts. In fact, to most people from the world of sport, speaking about the aesthetics of sport means to single out its beauty. Nevertheless, the construct of aesthetic value had been taking the place of beauty in contemporary aesthetics. This was important for two main reasons: i) it opened the possibility of new approaches to aesthetic reflection about contemporary art and to the consideration of other objects or activities in the scope of aesthetics, such as sports, and ii) it broadened the range of aesthetic categories able to explain the aesthetic value of the most unexpected and conspicuous artistic and aesthetic objects. The lecture is focused in transcendence considered as an aesthetic category that fosters understanding the aesthetic value of sport. Research about the subject will be presented (Lacerda, 2002; Ferreira, 2009; Lacerda and Graça, 2010) in order to support two main topics: transcendence and positive aesthetic value and transcendence and negative aesthetic value. References: Lacerda, T. (2002). Elementos para a construção de uma Estética do Desporto. Dissertação de Doutoramento. Porto, Faculdade de Desporto da Universidade do Porto. Lacerda, T., Graça, M.L. (2010). The ugly in sport. An exploratory essay about the aesthetics of the ugly. Ferreira, S. (2009). Estética do Desporto. Contributo para o esclarecimento desta temática a partir da perspectiva de atletas veteranos. Dissertação de Mestrado. Porto, Faculdade de Desporto da Universidade do Porto. Biosketch: Teresa Oliveira Lacerda is assistant professor with definitive nomination in the Faculty of Sport, University of Porto, Portugal. Responsible for several units in all of the three cycles of studies— graduation, master and doctoral courses—she is also responsible for the creation and development of the aesthetics of sport unit for all three cycles, and supervises Master and PhD dissertations. She is a member of the Centre for Research, Education, Innovation and Intervention in Sport (area of Sport, Education and Culture). Her research focuses on the aesthetics of sport. She has many international and national scientific publications as book chapters and journal articles. These include Education for the Aesthetics of Sport in Higher Education in the Sports Sciences. (2012, JPS), From Ode to Sport to Contemporary Aesthetic Categories of Sport: Strength Considered as an Aesthetic Category (2011, SEP), Da Estética do Desporto à Estética do Futebol (2011, RBCD), A Magia dos Jogos Desportivos e a Estética do Desporto (2007, RPCD), Uma Aproximação Estética ao Corpo Desportivo (2007, RPCD). She regularly holds sport in art exhibitions. She is a member of the editorial board of the Journal of the Philosophy of Sport and of Fair Play - Journal of Philosophy, Ethics and Law of Sport. She is a member of the Executive Council of the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport and vice president of the Latin Association for the Philosophy of Sport. 24 Signe Larsen and Kenneth Aggerholm Title: Between play and acrobatics - a phenomenological analysis of parkour Abstract: In parkour we see human beings perform a particular kind of bodily expertise on everyday street corners. They use benches, stairs and rails for expressive physical activity. Parkour has its origins in the French suburbs where it evolved as a subculture in the 1990s, and in recent years it has evolved on a worldwide scale. The dominant academic interpretations of parkour have described it as a form of critical and ideological play. To do parkour is in this view to practice an explicit critique of the modern and industrial city space and the dominance of Western ‘achievement sport’ (Eichberg 1998). Such analyses focus primary on a symbolicdiscursive level, where parkour is a performance of play that enlightens us (as spectators) of the social constitution of the urban space. In our paper we take a different starting point. Practitioners often articulate parkour as the learning of novel moves performed to pass efficiently and quickly through the city and as the ability to confront and overcome obstacles. To understand this we will present an existential phenomenological analysis of the bodily practice of traceurs with a focus on the lived experience of the practitioners. This is illuminated and analysed through Merleau-Ponty´s (1961) phenomenological concepts of motor intentionality, concrete and abstract movement, body schema and body space, and Peter Sloterdjik’s (2009, 2010) anthropology of practising. The analysis will also draw on cases from ethnographical fieldwork and interviews with Danish practitioners, and it will focus on the movement phenomena of play and acrobatics. In the article “Play disabilities” (2012) Scott Kretchmar points to the fact, that play depends on an ability to create an alternative relation to the world. In relation to this understanding parkour can be described as a playful way of setting aside the concrete movements that define normal or typical behaviour in our daily lives and put the objects of everyday spaces together in new and attractive configurations. However, parkour cannot be fully comprehended as only a playing practice, and the lived experience of traceurs can assist challenging the dichotomy between the “power of improvisation and joy” (paidia) and the “taste for gratuitous difficulty” (ludus) (Caillois 1961, 27). In parkour the subject struggles to overcome challenge and obstacles that are created through the alternative relation to different objects in spaces of everyday situations. Parkour involves an attractive vertical tension for breaking the perception of possible movements through reaching out for the impossible. The practitioners aim for a constant improvement of their bodily skills and their general ‘being-inthe-world’. Sloterdjik’s descriptions of acrobats and acrobatics allows analysing the effort to improve and refine movements as a genuine part of this kind of embodied practice, which is an (at least) equally important dimension as social critique and play. The analysis will in this way seek to enlighten our understanding of the practice of parkour, and it will at the same time put the phenomenological concepts to the test in order to refine our understanding of human practise and movement. References: Caillois, R. 1961. Man, Play and Games. Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press Eichberg, H. 1998. Body Cultures: Essays on Sport, Space and Idenitity. Kretchmar, S. 2012. Play Disabilities: A Reason for Physical Educators to Rethink the Boundaries of Special Education, Quest, 64 Merleau-Ponty, M. 1962. Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge Sloterdjik, P. 2013. You must change your life. Cambridge: Polity Press Professional and Contact Information Signe Højbjerre Larsen Institute of Sports Science and Clinical Biomechanics University of Southern Denmark [email protected] Kenneth Aggerholm- Postdoc Institute of Sports Science and Clinical Biomechanics University of Southern Denmark [email protected] 25 Cimin Liang Title: The Connotation of Cutting-Edge Sports Techniques Keywords: Connotation of Technique, Philosophy of Technique, Cutting-edge technique, Technique innovation, Abstract: Technology is one of the most complex social and cultural phenomenon that our humanity faces. Technology like a mountain with different image viewed from different side. This situation makes the concept being understood differently. The face of its portion is clearly seen from a location, while it becomes blurred and new aspect appears if the foothold changed. Many definitions of technology were shown from the sociological sense, the anthropological sense, the psychological sense, the sense of natural science, and of course the philosophical sense and sense of sports science, each with a unique knowledge and understanding and different from each other . This paper, limited the extension of “technique” to the “sports cutting-edge technique”, explores the connotation of the technique. A questionnaire was sent to sixty-four (64) experts in eight (8) different sports – artistic gymnastics, diving, rhythmic gymnastics, table tennis, volleyball, track and field, swimming and weight lifting. These experts, including Li Furong, Gao Jian, Deng Ruozeng, expressed their opinions about the outstanding features and developing trends of the modern sports cutting-edge techniques. The results of the study explain that sports cutting-edge techniques are the technical group at the highest level sports techniques, which has the following 6 A- class connotation characteristics: First, high personal technical style; Second, high competitive benefit in international arena; Third, high technique innovation Form; Fourth, high difficulty degree; Fifth, high investment of research & development; Sixth, high orientation of technique innovation. References [1] Cimin Liang On Frontier Technique of Competitive Sport, Beijing Sport University Press, Beijing, 2001, p.33-34 [2] Changyun Xu High Jump, On Success Law of China Advantage Sport Events, Chief editors:Yalong Xie, Ruying Wang, People’s Sport Publisher, Beijing, 1992, p 545 [3] Xiuwen Wu, Yingqiu Zhang. Techniques and Tactical of Top Table Tennis Players, Beijing Sport University Press, Beijing,1993,p.110 [4] Cimin Liang: Study on the Dynamic Change of Element Difficulty Level and Age Structure of Men Gymnasts Sport Science No. 4, 1993; On Frontier Technique of Competitive Sport, Beijing Sport University Press, 2001, p. 72-73 Professional and Contact Information Cimin Lianga, Ph. D. Boys Program Director Westside Dance and Gymnastics Academy [email protected]. Bo Liub, M.A. Lecturer, Physical Education Department Huanghe Science & Technology College [email protected] 26 Irena Martínková Title: Dangerous sport in phenomenology and analytical philosophy Keywords: Dangerous sport, phenomenology, analytical philosophy Abstract I shall briefly introduce the main characteristics of phenomenological and analytical approaches to sport, and with an example of dangerous sport I shall discuss how appropriate usage of both these approaches can describe a theme in a richer and more complete way. This paper compares approaches to dangerous sport by (1) the analytical tradition, as represented by Russell (2005), and (2) the phenomenological tradition, as examined by Müller (2008), showing the strenghts and weaknesses of both of these approaches. The strength of phenomenology is in its description of human existence and the structures of our experience, while the strength of analytical philosophy is in its clarification of common concepts and in its logical argumentation. In conclusion, I shall show how an appropirate combination of both could be enriching for the philosophy of sport. References MARTÍNKOVÁ, I. and HSU, L. (2009). Justification of Dangerous Sports and the Question of Values. Journal of Humanities and Social Sciences, 5(2), 93–99. MÜLLER, A. (2008). Risikosport: Suizid oder Lebenskunst? Hamburg: Merus. RUSSELL, J. S. (2005). The Value of Dangerous Sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 32(1), 1–19. Professional and Contact Information Irena Martínková Lecturer in the Philosophy of Sport Faculty of Physical Education and Sport Charles University in Prague [email protected] 27 Douglas McLaughlin Title: Winning Is Not the Only Good Thing: In Defense of Losing Keywords: Competition, winning, losing, Abstract: Recently, philosophers of sport have defended the merits of competition in response to its many critics. Bob Simon defends competition as a mutual quest for excellence through challenge. R. Scott Kretchmar and Tim Elcombe defend competition on the basis of an anthropological, phenomenological account that trumpets the values associated with the quest for victory. Excellences that are central to the purpose of competitive sport can be experienced in victory or defeat. Throughout the literature, philosophers of sport have made a variety of arguments both implicit and explicit pertaining to the virtues of competition. But does the sting of losing persist? A defense of competition that does not address in negative consequences of competition seems incomplete. The values associated with trying to win do not fully address the deep concerns about losing central to many criticisms of competition. By not considering the value of losing, recent arguments support competition for reasons that seem to be distinct from and in spite of the concerns associated with losing. But it is possible to make a strong defense of losing as being valuable in and of itself. This is quite distinct from concerns about competitors who purposely try to lose, which is a separate debate. But when competition is honestly pursued, losing is worthwhile in itself and provides value that directly justifies competition against it most ardent critics. The meaning of defeat resides in metaphysical and axiological considerations. The metaphysical considerations reside in the comparative nature of competition. In determining relative abilities, knowledge of results even in a loss provides the opportunity of self-knowledge. The axiological considerations reside in the response to losing. As a perfectionist practice, competitive sport requires striving for excellence. Losing provides valuable feedback in the effort to meaningfully and strategically pursue excellence in future competitions. The failure associated with losing is not absolute. Faced with humility and resiliency, losing is an opportunity for self-reflection and strategic self-improvement. Recognizing the value of losing not only directly diffuses criticisms of competition, but it presents new avenues for promoting meaningful experiences of sport. References: Nicholas Dixon, “On Winning and Athletic Superiority,” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 26 (1999): 10-26 R. Scott Kretchmar and Tim L. Elcombe, “In Defense of Competition and Winning: Revisiting Athletic Tests and Contest,” in Ethics in Sport, 2nd ed., ed. William J. Morgan (Champaign, IL: Human Kinetics, 2007): 181-194. Robert L. Simon. Fair Play: The Ethics of Sport (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2010). Professional and Contact Information Doug McLauglin Assistant professor California State University Northridge [email protected] 28 Michael J. McNamee Conference Keynote Address Title: Paralympism and the limits of biotechnology Keywords: Paralympic, Paralympism, elective surgery, disability, ethics Abstract: In this presentation I critically discuss four real cases arising from Paralympic sports. Two involve the use of legitimate therapeutic interventions that additionally have enhancement effects in sports, specifically arising in the cases of (1) botulinim toxin injections to decrease muscle spasticity and (2) achilles tendon lengthening surgery to ease gait. The third and fourth cases involve amputation of limbs that either (3) enhance sporting performance; or (4) enable disability sport membership of an otherwise able bodied person, by the use of elective, non–clinically indicated, amputation surgery . I evaluate the cases ethically, offering suitable policy responses in cases 1 and 2 to enable these athletes to participate, while arguing that in Cases 3 and 4 that although individuals may have entitlements to body modification surgery under Mill’s ‘harm principle', it does not follow that organisers must accept their participation in events such as the Paralympic Games. I situate these cases in the context of the IPC’s four stated values: courage, determination, inspiration and equality. I argue that disability sports organisations, including the International Paralympic Committee, should ban such practices and better articulate their value base in order to preserve the integrity of disability sports. Biosketch: Mike McNamee is Professor of Applied Ethics in the College of Engineering at Swansea University, Professor Chaire Olympique Henri de Baillet Latour & Jacques Rogge 2013-14 at the University of Ghent/Université Catholique de Louvain, Belgium, and Visiting Professor 2013-16 at Hunan Normal University, China. He is Founding Editor (2007) of the international research journal Sport, Ethics, and Philosophy; previously he served on the Editorial Board of Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 2000-7. He is Editor of Routledge's books series "Ethics and Sports" (with Jim Parry). His books include Sport, Medicine, Ethics (2014) Reader in Sports Ethics (2011, Editor); Sports, Virtues and Vices (2008, Routledge). He is a former President of the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport, a member of the Association since 1991, Founding Chair of the British Philosophy of Sport Association, and the Vice President of the European Association for the Philosophy of Sport. He is married to Cheryl and has two lovely daughters: Megan and Ffion. He plays tennis and golf and runs regularly. 29 Sam Morris Title: Moral Luck and the Talent Problem Keywords: moral luck, constitutive luck, circumstantial luck, talent Abstract: My objective in this project is to explore the concept of moral luck as it relates to sports. I am not especially interested in resultant luck. Rather, my attention is more closely with constitutive and circumstantial luck. As a foundation I draw from both Bernard Williams’ and Thomas Nagel’s classic handling of moral luck, generally. Within the philosophy of sport are similar explorations of this nexus by Robert Simon and David Carr that also factor into the present work. My intent is to put a new lens in front of a puzzle drawn from Torbjörn Tännsjö’s well-known article “Is Our Admiration of Sports Heroes Facistoid?” Specifically, the idea that we might admire an athlete who excels without having worked hard for it (i.e., though talent per se). If we may call this puzzle “the talent problem,” the questions driving the present work are as follows: 1| what is the relationship between moral luck and the talent problem, and 2| can this relationship provide a prescription for morally assessing the talent problem? References: Simon, Robert. “Deserving to be Lucky: Reflections of the Role of Luck and Desert in Sports.” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 34 (2007): 13-25. Tännsjö, Torbjörn. “Is Our Admiration of Sports Heroes Fascistoid?” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 25 (1998): 23-34. Williams, Bernard and Thomas Nagel. “Moral Luck.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 50 (1976): 115-151. Professional and Contact Information Sam P. Morris, Ph.D., Clinical Faculty Miami University Kinesiology and Health Sport Leadership and Management [email protected] 30 David Myers Title: The aesthetic properties of competitiveness Keywords: aesthetics, sport, game, competition Abstract: Here I address how competitiveness affects the aesthetic in sports and games. While sports and games may be considered separate entities elsewhere, I consider them equally here as regards their competitive nature. This is, to some extent, well-trodden ground. Positions already drawn are that competition precludes the aesthetic in sport (e. g., Best, 1974, 1980) and, conversely, that competition provides, even is necessary, for the aesthetic in sport (e. g., see Kupfer, 1975 as regards sport, and Humble, 1993 as regards game). Complicating matters further is that some consider competitiveness intrinsic to sport, or, at the very least, “the great majority of sport” (Best, 1980, p. 70); others consider competitiveness but one of other, equally defining characteristics of sports and games (Vossen, 2004). This complication allows for intermediate positions asserting that the aesthetic in sports and games is sometimes affected by competitiveness and sometimes not -- but not necessarily so. In this essay, I consider competitiveness a critically defining characteristic of sports and games, broadly, as Kupfer (1975) does regarding sport -- i. e., as activity devoted to “overcoming opposition” (p. 84) -- and as Suits (2005) does regarding games -- i. e., as means “only permitted by rules, where rules prohibit more efficient in favour of less efficient means” (pp. 48-9). With this move of interpreting rules-determined prohibitions in sports and games as oppositions to overcome, I argue that the competitive-based purposiveness of sports coincides closely with that of games. I then interpret the persistence of those intermediate and ambivalent positions regarding the influence of competitiveness on aesthetics as an indication that sports and games require a certain sort of editing -- by participants and spectators alike -- in order to access and reveal their unique aesthetic properties. This editing process is dictated by the uncertainty of outcome -- randomness -- that is fundamentally and necessarily associated with competitiveness, which simultaneously defines and produces the aesthetic in sports and games. Thus, some of the inconsistencies observed in attempts to conceptualize the aesthetic in sports and games may well be consistent with attributing their aesthetic properties to competitiveness. References: Best, D. (1974). The aesthetic in sport. British Journal of Aesthetics, 14(3), 197-213. Best, D. ( 1980). Art and sport. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 14(2), 69-80. Humble, P. N. (1993). Chess as an art form. British Journal of Aesthetics, 33(1), 59. Kupfer, J. (1975). Purpose and beauty in sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 2(1), 83-90. Suits, B. (2005). The grasshopper. Peterborough, Ontario, Canada: Broadview Press. Vossen, D. (2004). The nature and classification of games. Avante, 10(1), 53-68. Professional and Contact Information David Myers Professor of Mass Communication Loyola University New Orleans USA [email protected] 31 Arvi Pakaslahti Title: Series, Ranking Systems and Betterness Keywords: Series, ranking systems, betterness, goal difference, meta contests Abstract: It could be argued that it is important or desirable that the official result of a sports contest is such that it reflects at least reasonably well the betterness of the teams or athletes in that contest (i.e. that it reflects at least reasonably well how much athletic excellence the teams or athletes showed in that contest compared to each other). Thus it could be argued that there should be at least a reasonably good “fit” between the betterness of the athletes or teams in some sports contest and the official result of that contest. I call this view the Fittingness Ideal about Betterness. Sports contests can be divided into individual contests and meta contests (see Loland 2002, 99). Meta contests can be divided into series, knockout contests and contests which are a mixture of a series and a knockout contest (see Loland 2002, 99-102). It seems to me clear that series are, from the point of view of the Fittingness Ideal about Betterness, better than the two other types of meta contests. This is so because in series (bad) luck tends to affect the final placings of the athletes or teams less than in the two other types of meta contests.In each meta contest some kind of system is used for determining the final placings of the athletes or teams that participated in that contest. Each such system may be called a ranking system. In this paper I identify and discuss three different kinds of ranking systems that can be used in a series in a team ball game. In simple point-orientated ranking systems and complex point-orientated ranking systems points gathered by different teams from wins, draws and losses determine the placings of the teams, except in those cases in which two or more teams have the same amount of points. The difference between simple point-orientated ranking systems and complex point-orientated ranking systems is that in the former a team always gets the same amount of points from each win, draw and loss (e.g. three, one and zero), whereas in a complex point-orientated ranking system a team does not always get the same amount of points from each win, draw and/or loss (e.g. some wins may be worth three points and some two points). In goal difference-orientated ranking systems, on the other hand, the goal difference (or equivalent in those team ball games in which goals do not exist) of each team determines the placings of the teams, except in those cases in which two or more teams have the same goal difference. My discussion of these three ranking systems consists of two parts. First, I discuss which one of them is the best one from the point of view of the Fittingness Ideal about Betterness. Secondly, I discuss whether the ranking system that is the best from the point of view of the Fittingness Ideal about Betterness faces such problems that all things considered it should be rejected in favour of one of the other ranking systems. Bibliography Loland, Sigmund (2002): Fair Play in Sport. Routledge, London. Torres, Cesar R. & Peter F. Hager (2005): “Competitive Sport, Evaluation Systems, and Just Results: The Case of Rugby Union’s Bonus-Point System”, Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, Vol. 32, 208-222. Torres, Cesar R. & Peter F. Hager (2007): “Just Evaluation Systems in Competitive Sport”, Journal of Physical Education, Recreation & Dance, Vol. 78, 27-32. Professional and Contact Information Arvi Pakaslahti, Junior researcher Public Choice Research Centre University of Turku, Finland [email protected] 32 Jim Parry Title: On Biting in Sport - The case of Luis Suárez Key Words: biting, Suárez, assault, consent, harm, sport rules Abstract: So: the Uruguayan footballer Luis Suárez has confessed, apologised and given assurances as to future good behaviour, after his World Cup assault on the Italian defender Chiellini. There were three immediate excuses and mitigations offered, which we dismiss: It was inconsequential It was no different from many other ‘assaults’ It was not particularly serious Our central question has a different focus: we want to ask what makes biting in sport such a bad thing, especially since it does not seem always to threaten as much harm to opponents as some other practices. We examine the place of biting in sports rules, especially in combat and contact sports, and the role of consent and criminal liability, before moving to consider when and why biting is seen as unacceptable. We consider arguments from harm (direct and indirect), skin penetration (bodily integrity and transgression), ‘dirty fighting’ and animalism. Finally, we consider the topical case of Luis Suárez, distinguishing reactive from proactive biting, and reactive from instrumental behaviour. We also consider arguments that offer psychological and cultural mitigation, and we assess the justice of FIFA’s punishment. We conclude that: there is at least a case to be considered that Suárez’ actions were intended to be consequential, and that biting is different from other types of assault, especially in contact games biting is the kind of assault to the possibility of which participants do not consent, so that it is actionable in criminal law. whilst psychological and cultural ‘explanations’ may shed some light on background, motivations and attitudes, they do not affect the above points, and provide no excuse or mitigation. our further explanations for the unacceptability of biting in sport – i.e. that it threatens harm, is ‘dirty’, transgressive and animalistic – go some way to indicate ways in which such practices might compromise the potential of sport for moral education In final comments, we argue that there was no unfairness or unjustifiable harshness in Suárez’ punishment, that no serious issues were raised in employment law, and that FIFA bore no special responsibility for the treatment (if, indeed, that were appropriate) and rehabilitation of the player. Indeed, we argue, the onus is on Suárez to demonstrate that he can be an acceptable opponent. Professional and Contact Information Prof Jim Parry FTVS, Charles University in Prague, Czech Republic Email: [email protected] 33 Jose-Luis Perez-Triviño Title: Sport Enhancement: from Natural Doping to Brain Stimulation Keywords: doping, enhancement, neurosciencie, brain stimulation, Abstract: Doping, or in more morally neutral terms, enhancement, has always been present in sport practice and not only at the present time, which is marked by professionalism and competitiveness. The latest development in doping seems linked to biotechnological advances, and one of the techniques that will apparently be particularly important in the near future is neuroscience, notably transcranial stimulators. These devices promise to improve not only physiological aspects in sport performance, but also mental and emotional ones. On the other hand, they can seriously affect sport ethics insofar as they can be economically accessible to professional and amateur athletes. References: Berghmans Ron, ter Meulen R., Malizia A.& Vos R. (2011). Scientific, ethical, and social issues in mood enhancement. Savulescu J. Ter Meulen, R. & Kahane G. (eds.) Enhancing Human Capacities. Oxford; Blackwell. Davis, N. J. (2013). Neurodoping: Brain Stimulation as a Performance-Enhancing Measure. Sports Medicine, 43 (8), doi:10.1007/s40279-013-0027-z Eronia, O. (2012). Doping mentale and concetto di salute: a possibile regolamentazione legislative? Archivio penale, 3. Foddy, B. (2011). “Enhancing Skill”. Savulescu J. Ter Meulen, R. & Kahane G. (eds.) Enhancing Human Capacities. Oxford; Blackwell. Goodall, S., Howatson, G., Romer, L., & Ross, E. (2012). Transcranial magnetic stimulation in sport science: A commentary. European Journal of Sport Science. doi:10.1080/17461391.2012.704079 Hoberman, J. (1992). Mortal Engines. The Science of Performance and the Dehumanization of Sport. New York:The Free Press. Holme, S. & McNamee, M. (2011). Physical Enhancement: what Baseline, Whose Judgment?Savulescu J. Ter Meulen, R. & Kahane G. (eds.) Enhancing Human Capacities. Oxford; Blackwell. Housden, Ch.R.. Morein-Zamir, S. & Sahakian, B.J, (2011). “Cognitive Enhancing Drugs: Neuroscience and Society” iSavulescu, J.-Ter Meulen, R.-Kahane, G. (eds.) Enhancing Human Capacities. Oxford; Blackwell. Kanai R, Chaieb L, Antal A, Walsh V. & Paulus W. (2008). Frequency-dependent electrical stimulation of the visual cortex. Curr Biol. 18(23). LeUnes, A. (2011). Sport Psychology. London:Icon Books. Miah, A. (2011). Physical Enhancement: The State of Art. Savulescu J. Ter Meulen, R. & Kahane G. (eds.) Enhancing Human Capacities. Oxford; Blackwell. Pérez-Triviño, J.L. (2011). Gene Doping and the Ethics of Sport: Between Enhancement and Posthumanism"; International Journal of Sports Science 2011; 1 (1). Pérez-Triviño, J.L. (2013). “Cyborgsportpersons: Between Disability and Enhancement; Physical Culture and Sport. Studies and Research. 57, (1). Sandberg, A. (2011). Cognition Enhancement: Upgrading the Brain. Savulescu, J.-Ter Meulen, R.& Kahane, G. (eds.) Enhancing Human Capacities. Oxford; Blackwell. Sandel, M. (2007). The case against Perfection, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (USA) Professional and Contact Information Jose-Luis Perez-Triviño Associate professor of Philosophy of Law (Pompeu Fabra University). President of “Spanish Association of Philosophy of Sport” Director of “Fair Play. Journal of Philosophy, Ethics and Sports Law” [email protected] 34 Zuzanna Rucinska Title: Radically Enacted Creativity in Sports Key Words: Creativity, Imagination, Sensorimotor, Enactivism, Affordances Abstract “Tactical creativity” (Memmert et al. 2010) is a useful skill in sports, though hard to achieve. For example, in the in situation of attacking or advancing (as opposed to defending), on-the-spot ‘creative’ maneuver that can surprise the defendant is beneficial to the game. As Memmert & Roth (2007) claim, “creativity entails varying, rare and flexible decision-making in complex game situations… (but) it is not clear how this type of thinking is developed.” This paper will challenge the common assumptions in cognitive sciences and sports psychology that creativity (or creative improvisation) requires conceptual thinking or that it is explicitly representational in character. Instead, I will propose a notion of radically enacted creativity, a result of using one’s sensorimotor skills (coupling of perception and action) on exploring contextual affordances and participating in shared activities. It is the idea that creativity can be conceptualized as putting experiences (not ideas) together in a new way, which is an embodied and enacted skill. I will argue that tactical creativity in sports should be understood as such enactive capacity, giving reasons why it is unattractive to believe in mental motor plans or imaginings (van Leeuwen 2011) as guiding creative behaviours. This approach expands the philosophical repertoire that others have discussed regarding creativity and sport in the discipline (Aggerholm 2013; Zimmerman & Chung-Saura 2013). I will first discuss the criteria of creativity in sport psychology: originality, flexibility, fluency of thinking (in Memmert et al., 2010), and discuss them in light of two very different philosophical proposals: traditional Representational Models (RM) of creativity, and the new proposal of Radically Enactive (RE) creativity. I will challenge the RM approach and suggest why RE approach is a viable alternative, if not a more promising one, to understanding emergence and development of creativity. I will also discuss and rebut potential challenges to the RE account (such as the argument that dealing with the absent and the abstract requires representations), arguing for the role of environmental and social affordances and narrative scaffolds as sufficient explanans of some imaginative and creative behaviours as the ones found in sports contexts. The paper will conclude that radically enactive creativity serves as a good predictive model of improvement and innovation in creating new sports tactics. In terms of applied sport philosophy, I will propose suggestions to coaches of how RE creativity could be developed, basing on the success of this approach in other domains like stage acting and family therapy. References: Van Leeuwen, N. (2011). Imagination is Where the Action Is. The Journal of Philosophy, 108(2), 55-77. Hutto, D.D. and Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content. Cambridge: MIT Press. Bishop, J.M. and Martin, A.O. (Eds.) (2014). Contemporary Sensorimotor Theory, Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics Vol. 15. Switzerland: Springer International Publishing. Professional and Contact Information Zuzanna Rucinska PhD candidate at the University of Hertfordshire, UK Early-Stage Researcher of the Marie-Curie Initial Training Network ‘TESIS’ [email protected] 35 John S. Russell Waren Fraleigh Distinguished Scholar Lecture Title: Resiliance Abstract: This paper argues that resilience is the central virtue in sport and a cardinal virtue in a human life. These large claims are made more striking by the fact that resilience is an overlooked virtue. It has gone generally unnoticed by virtue theorists and received no systematic treatment by sport philosophers. Yet it is difficult to think of a human life succeeding without drawing on this virtue, and it is particularly fundamental to taking on the challenges that sport presents. The phenomenon of human resilience has, nevertheless, been studied extensively over the past 50 years by psychologists, including sport psychologists. But this research lacks clarity about the concept of resilience and makes no effort to connect empirical findings regarding human resilience to virtue theory. This paper draws, in part, on the psychologists' research to clarify the concept of resilience, explain its fundamental role in sport, and how it fits broadly within a classical conception of virtue. These efforts shed light on the special value of sport to its participants and its role in human culture and progress. The centrality of resilience to sport also suggests that sport requires a conception of virtue that is not merely an extension of classical or contemporary cardinal virtues. Sport may require its own distinctive listing and ordering of virtues. Thus, reflection on the role of resilience in sport may help to inform and encourage development of a distinctive theory of virtue in sport. Biosketch John Russell teaches philosophy at Langara College in Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada. He has edited the Journal for the Philosophy of Sport for 8 years and has published widely in philosophy of sport. He is 2014 Warren P. Fraleigh Distinguished Scholar and received the IAPS Distinguished Service Award in 2012. 36 Takuya Sakamoto Title: The Body of the Sports Coach as Site of Existential Meaning Keywords: Human body, existential meaning, educational relationship, anger Abstract: This study aims to elucidate the mode of being of the body of the sport coach as her/his existential meaning. Existential meaning means the sport coach’s raison d’etre which is acquired implicitly by her/himself. I show a new perspective concerning this kind of existence for the sport coach or PE teacher. The human body is discussed relying on phenomenological theories of the body, which include Merleau-Ponty. Human body theory has shown that the human body not only functions as medical and physiological soma but also plays significant roles in human existence and human relationships. An existential viewpoint offers many possibilities concerning the human body as site of existential meaning for individuals. In this light, the body of the sport coach can be examined in terms of how it acquires her/his existential meaning in sport coaching and PE class. Past research has failed to focus on this, yet it seems that in sport instruction and PE, ‘who instructs?’ is as equally or more important than ‘how do we instruct?’ This is shown to be so because the very same instruction and method do not necessarily lead to the same results. For this reason, the individual existential meaning of the sport coach could be a significant topic in sport philosophy. Many phenomenologists have argued for the importance of the human body, as Merleau-Ponty evinces. His views are prominent here, but additionally two other thinkers are engaged: 1. Heidegger. While, as Sartre commented, Heidegger discussed the body insufficiently in Being and Time, his late lecture, Zollikon Seminars, provides a fuller description of the existential aspect of the human body. As Aho (2009) points out, the relation between Heidegger’s late insight and Merleau-Ponty’s one has not been sufficiently examined. Presently, I explore this connection. 2. Van Manen. He is a phenomenologist of education who points out the significance of phenomenology as a method to describe educational practice. He does not discuss sport or PE directly, however his educational viewpoint provides effective suggestions to examine existentially not only players but also sport coaches and PE teachers. He shows specifically the importance of an existential perspective in educational relationships. Accordingly, I consider the existential meaning of the coach’s body and, especially, focus on ‛anger’as an existential bodily action. This phenomenon, anger, is generally understood as the expression of an inner psychological state. Merleau-Ponty, however, understands it as an existential bodily action of the individual human being. In light of this understanding, the ‘anger’ often expressed by sport coaches or PE teachers toward players or students could be understood as a phenomenon that closely engages the mode of her/his existence beyond mere psychological meaning. Additionally, since phenomenological theory of the human body is always aware of human relationships, the argument of existential bodily action of sport coaches enables us to extend the discussion to the player’s existential status. In other words, examining the existential meaning of the body of the sport coach could shed new light on how a human being’s existence engages in sport. References: Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012) Phenomenology of Perception (NY, Routledge). Heidegger, M.: Boss, M. (ed.) (2001) Zollikon Seminars: Protocol Conversations Letters (Evanston, Northern University Press). Van Manen, M. (1990) Researching Lived Experience (Albany, NY, State University of New York Press). Professional and Contact Information Takuya Sakamoto, Assistant professor, Meisei University, Tokyo, JAPAN [email protected], 37 Masami Sekine & Takayuki Hata Title: Anthropology of Solidarity: From Defeat to Existential Solidarity Keywords: win and defeat, self-overcoming, achieving solidarity Abstract: The aim of victory is structurally incorporated in sporting matches (competitions). Even without the intention of winning, it is still possible for a player to obtain a victorious outcome (although in the overwhelming majority of cases, it will be that a player will crave victory while being unable to attain it). Here the problem is not with the spirit or psychology of the players, but with the structure of the game or match itself. If we analyze the problem of this structure, we will notice one thing, namely, the fact that in a given race or match, only one player (or one team) can achieve complete victory, i.e., it is the structure that produces a solitary winner and a multitude with the experience of defeat. In a tournament with 100 participants, only one will emerge victorious; in an athletics race, only 1 of the 8 finalists can be the winner. Although sports are said to be the pursuit of excellence (P. Weiss, 1969; R. Simon, 1991), what do sports bring to the majority of humans who are not winners, when victory cannot be achieved by all? When excellence is not necessarily the reward, could it be that humanity also has something to gain from defeat? Generally, in the real world, defeat leads to the loss of many things such as money, honor, and social status. For some athletes and teams, a loss in the finals might retain some realistic form of profit to some extent such as prize money for runners-up or a record as a contender in the final match. Still, even they will have foregone the possibility of profit that might have been obtained in victory. However, while to suffer defeat may entail the loss of some things, it is not the loss of all things. It may sound strange to say that sports are an activity in which humanity gains something from defeat. Even with decisive defeats where the evaluation of onlookers does not extend even to participants’ evaluation as taking part “in the mutual pursuit of excellence,” there yet remains a chance for humanity. From this study, the first conclusion to be drawn is that in accepting an attitude of defeat, we grant our inner selves opportunities for “selfovercoming,” which is separate from victory. Defeat is not something to be celebrated, and nor is it a subject to take comfort from. Rather, it is a starting point from which we begin to overcome ourselves. As a second conclusion, we might say as follows. Focus on a course of methodical action and selfovercoming exist not “outcomes” but as “processes.” Here, we focus on actions and self-overcoming can be reported as the specific content of spiritual satisfaction (inner fulfillment) in and of themselves. References: Nietzsche, F. (2005). Thus spoke Zarathustra: a book for everyone and nobody (G. Parkes, (Trans.). New York: Oxford University Press. Weiss, P. (1969). Sport: a philosophic inquiry. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press Simon, R. L. (1991). Fair play: sports, values, and society. Boulder, CO: Westview Press Personal and Contact Information Takayuki Hata Faculty of Education Nagasaki University [email protected] Masami Sekine Faculty of Education Okayama University [email protected] 38 Tara Smith Title: “Something to Behold: The Spiritual Value of Art and Sport” Key words: value and spiritual value; autoelicity (end in itself); spectatorship; meaning; comprehensive world view (personal philosophy of life) Abstract: This paper will explore the most fundamental similarities and differences in the value of art and the value of sport (principally, value for the audience). Many have observed that the realms of art and sport share several common features (their intensification of ordinary experience, their isolation from utilitarian practicality, the passions aroused, displays of great skill, sense of community, ritualistic components, etc.). In terms of capturing the core value of each enterprise, however, these similarities are relatively superficial. This paper will posit a more fundamental common dimension: the way in which both sport and art offer spiritual values – in particular, by making materially manifest certain abstract ideas. It will address both how they do this and why this is a genuine value. In tracing this, however, we will also see how art and sport manifest abstractions in somewhat differing ways, such that the exact spiritual values available from each are distinct. Thus I will also explain these differences. Sport, as is widely recognized, offers the display of many valuable traits of personal character, such as discipline, resilience, poise under pressure, or strategic ingenuity. I will argue that art, by contrast, provides a different order of value: the tangible, perceptible presentation of a philosophical worldview. Human beings go about their lives – and need to go about their lives – on the basis of an at least implicit, comprehensive “big picture” outlook on life – a set of basic suppositions about the nature of the playing field in which we pursue our various ends. Put a little differently, we operate with a set of working hypotheses concerning what is real in life and what is reliable, concerning what is important and what is possible or doable. Individual works of art put such worldviews on display, objectifying them in existential reality, on the canvas or on the stage. In sport, the spiritual values exhibited are comparatively circumscribed (resilience, poise, and so on). While there is definite value in witnessing the realization of such traits, it is a different kind of value than that which art offers. While this may suggest that art is the greater value, we will also observe certain values of sport that art, as a kind, does not offer (specifically, concerning the nature of the traits that are celebrated in sport, and the actual, as opposed to the “fictional,” character of many of its values). I shall also consider the possibility that on a different plane, sport does affirm a worldview – not by means of anyone’s “making a statement” in the way that an artist conveys themes through a sculpture or a poem, but through the very nature and structure of athletic competition. The point, in the end, is not to rank the values of art and sport, but to better understand the exact – and significant – spiritual values offered by each. References: Randolph Feezel, Sport, Philosophy, & Good Lives, 2013, chapter 8 “Sport and the Question of the Meaning of Life” Stephen Mumford, Watching Sport: Aesthetics, Ethics and Emotions, London: Routledge, 2011. Tim L. Elcombe, “Sport, Aesthetic Experience, and Art as the Ideal Embodied Metaphor,” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, volume 39, no. 2, October 2012 Professional and Contact Information Tara Smith Professor, Department of Philosophy University of Texas at Austin [email protected] 39 Sarah Teetzel Title: Protecting Child Athletes in Sport Keywords: Paternalism, Eligibility, Children Abstract: The philosophy of childhood literature demonstrates that children are a vulnerable population in need of special consideration and protection. Scholars and legislators have argued that children have not yet developed the capacity to make rational, independent decisions, and, as a result, their guardians must make paternalistic decisions for them in their best interests. International agreements, such as the Convention on the Rights of the Child, recognize the unique status of children and their need for protection (David, 2012). In sport, rules, regulations, and policies are in place to protect child athletes from violence, exploitation, over-training, and coercion. Policies such as the International Olympic Committee’s Consensus Statement on Training the Child Athlete and the World Anti-Doping Agency’s stipulations regarding minors in the World Anti-Doping Code function to protect child athletes’ rights and open futures. Rule 43 in the Olympic Charter states the International Olympic Committee does not impose age limits for competitors; however, the rule also contains the clause that an International Federation can restrict events to athletes of specific ages as long as the IOC Executive Board approves the eligibility constraint. Past problems with very young gymnasts and figure skaters rising to the top level of sport led to the enforcement of minimum age criteria in certain sports. There is considerable discrepancy in the minimum and maximum age limits across the events contested at both the Olympic Games and the Youth Olympic Games. As a result, young athletes can compete in some sports at the highest levels, but not in others. Yet age limits only restrict young athletes’ eligibility to enter competitions and cannot control the quantity or intensity of their training. Drawing on the work of Tymowksi (2000) and Dixon (2007), as well as past decisions involving minors implemented by the International Olympic Committee and the Court of Arbitration for Sport, this paper argues that international sports organizations are not doing enough to protect child athletes. Moreover, this paper argues from a consequentialist perspective that the existence of Youth Olympic Games exacerbates these problems. References: David, P. (2012).Ensuring the human rights of young athletes. In Sport, Ch ldren’ R ght nd V olence Prevention, eds C. Brackenridge, T. Kay, & D. Rhind, 161-163. London: Brunel University. Dixon, N. (2007). Sport, parental autonomy, and children’s right to an open future. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, 34 (2), 147-159. Tymowski, G. (2000). Rights and wrongs: Children’s participation in high-performance sports. In Cross Cultural Perspectives in Child Advocacy, eds. I. R. Berson, M. J. Berson, & B. C. Cruz. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing. Professional and Contact Information Sarah Teetzel Assistant Professor University of Manitoba [email protected], 40 Yumi Terayama Title: Consideration of learning contents for dance in the Japanese Physical Education Curriculum KeyWords: Physical education, Dance education, Intention, expression Abstract: This presentation discusses a unique conception of physical and dance education in Japan, “taiiku” (Physical Education) and intends to discuss and argue for its unique conception of education through movement. In Japan, “taiiku” (physical education) is implemented from elementary school to the university. The “taiiku” aims neither at teaching sport nor dance, but rather it seeks to emphasize that it is important to educate the body through sport or dance. It is because it will be said that what is necessary is just to entrust a private sports club and visualize public benefit of community sports club if what is necessary is just to teach a sport and a dance as it is and it will become. So, in a “taiiku” class the learning contents which contribute to a student's physical education must be examined by using sport and dance as teaching materials. The next idea that is explored presently inquire into the contents of study of a particular dance style. Probably, given any dance style or choreography, many people imagine that it is simply reduced to the choreography that a teacher gives the students. However, it is not limited to this. Rather, the teacher will teach how to dance and concurrently use the dance as teaching method. However, this does not mean teaching anything through dance, but instead it shows only how to move in and through dance. A crucial element in this process is the element of expression through movements, for example, which is necessary for dance. It is accompanied by a confirming process of the dancer’s intention and his/her own movements. This process entails a communication between dance teacher and students, and in dance includes the creation that arises from the exchange between them. I think it is important to make students aware of their own "intention" through this process, fully utilizing the essence of dance for this purpose. For this reason, it will-be important to build into the learning contents the process of training the body, accompanied by communications skills and the goal to enhance the students’ power of expression. In other words, in a dance class, it is vital to pay attention to the interrelationships between learners, rather than only focusing on providing learners with existing motor skills, such as specific dance steps. References Margaret N. H. Doubler (1957) Dance: A Creative Art Experience. University of Wisconsin Press Edmund Husserl (2012 : first publishedin1931) Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology (Routledge Classics). Routledge, NY Maxine Sheets (1979) On Movement and Objects in Motion: The Phenomenology of the Visible in Dance. Journal of Aesthetic Education13 (2): 33-46. Professional and Contact Information Yumi Terayama Associate Professor University of Tsukuba [email protected] 41 Cesar Torres Title: Boxing and the Youth Olympic Games Keywords: Youth Olympic Games, boxing, health, autonomy, Olympism Abstract: The Youth Olympic Games (YOG) were inaugurated in 2010 and constitute not only the International Olympic Committee’s (IOC) latest enterprise but also the largest multisport international event for young athletes. Its Competitive Program is based on that of the Olympic Games, but with fewer disciplines and events while also featuring some unique new disciplines such as the basketball three-on-three tournament and other innovations such as the inclusion of contests for mixed-gender teams. Although the YOG are intended for athletes between 15 and 18 years of age, each International Sport Federation determines a specific age bracket for its sport. In the case of boxing, the second YOG to be held in Nanjing, China later this year will include 78 boxers (60 men and 18 women) between 17 and 18 years of age competing in ten and three categories for men and women, respectively. The motivation for the YOG is as much the athletic competition as the values that have inspired and framed the Olympic Games since their inception in the late nineteenth century, a vision known as “Olympism.” Thus, as former IOC President Jacques Rogge articulated before the inaugural YOG, “The main goal . . . is not competition as such. The main goal is to give the youngsters an education based on Olympic values.”2 In other words, the YOG have been envisioned as a sizeable and unique Olympic pedagogical effort. At the very core of the YOG is the attempt to familiarize young athletes with Olympism and its values “in a fun and festive spirit and to raise awareness of important issues such as the benefits of a healthy lifestyle, the fight against doping, global challenges and their role as sports ambassadors in their communities.”3 In this regard, the IOC announced in a press release following its Executive Board approval of the YOG in 2007 that “Sports events would be carefully chosen to protect the health of the young athletes.”4 In this presentation I will argue that boxing is not a suitable sport to advance the professed goals of the YOG and that it should be removed from the event’s Competitive Program. One line of argument will focus on the questionable impact of boxing on the health of young athletes. Issues of autonomy, consent, and paternalism will be discussed in relation to the health of these athletes. In this regard, I will argue not only that boxing is deleterious to the health of young athletes but also that these athletes might not possess the level of autonomy required to allow them to practice a sport with such an inherent risk of serious, and even irreparable, harm. A second line of argument will focus on the central purpose of boxing and its relation to Olympism and its values. This will allow to me argue that boxing is a violent-prone sport incoherent with Olympic values. In the end, the educational aspiration of the YOG can be accomplished more effectively through other sports better aligned with the values of Olympism. References: Douglas W. McLaughlin and Cesar R. Torres, “More than Games. Olympism as a Moral Approach to Sport,” in The Olympics and Philosophy, eds., Heather L. Reid and Michael W. Austin (Lexington, KY: The University Press of Kentucky, 2012), 101-116. Nicholas Dixon, “Boxing, Paternalism and Legal Moralism,” Social Theory and Practice 27 (2001): 323-345. Paul Davis, “Ethical Issues in Boxing,” Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 20/21 (1993/1994): 48-63. Professional and Contact Information Cesar R. Torres Professor Department of Kinesiology, Sport Studies, and Physical Education The College at Brockport, State University of New York [email protected] Stephen Wade, “No kidding: Teens to get Youth Olympic Games,” USA Today, April 25, 2010, http://w ww.us atoday.com/sports/olympics/2007-04-25-2774646336_x.htm (accessed November 1, 2010). 3 International Olympic Committee, Youth and Olympism. Olympic Studies Centre Content Package (Lausanne: International Olympic Committee, 2010), 5. 4 See International Olympic Committee, “IOC Executive Board Welcomes Idea of Youth Olympic Games,” April 26, 2007, http://www.olympic.org/content/news/media-resources/manual-news/1999-200 9/2007/04/26/ioc-executive-board-welcomes-idea-ofyouth-olympic-games/ (accessed November 1, 2010). 2 42 Charlene Weaving Title: A girl on the beach as the cure for nothingness”: Examining 50 years of ‘beautiful’ in Sports Illustrated Swimsuit Issue Key Words: Sexualization, Sports Illustrated, female athletes Abstract: This year marks the 50th Anniversary of the Sports Illustrated Swimsuit Issue (SISI). In 1964, in order to fill the void in sport news in between football bowl games and baseball spring training coverage, the first official swimsuit issue featuring ‘bathing beauties’ was created. To commemorate this special anniversary, a hard cover coffee table book was published and the American television network NBC aired a two-hour special celebrating the SISI franchise, describing it as the “one of the most hotly anticipated annual fixtures in American pop culture.” Numerous female athletes have appeared as models in SISI such as Danica Patrick, Lindsey Vonn, the Williams sisters and Amanda Beard. Using a content analysis approach, I will argue that celebrating the 50th Anniversary of SISI is problematic for the continued struggle for women in sport, especially given the prominence of sexual objectification. Specifically, I have developed five arguments that demonstrate the problematic features of SISI. I attempt to provide the first sport philosophical analysis of SISI and build on the work of sport sociologist Laurel R. Davis who, in 1997, published “The Swimsuit Issue and Sport: Hegemonic Masculinity in Sports Illustrated.” Davis’s research received many accolades and is revered in the sport sociology domain. The SISI has evolved over the years from a bathing suit fashion spread to a contemporary multimedia colossal. For example, to help celebrate the 50th anniversary, SISI teamed up with Mattel and features Sports Illustrated Swimsuit Barbie in the February 2014 issue, and a special collector’s item Barbie doll was produced and sold exclusively at Target. The theme of the campaign is “Unapologetic”. Mattel indicates, “As a legend herself, and under constant criticism about her body and how she looks, posing in the issue gives Barbie and her fellow legends an opportunity to own who they are, celebrate what they have done and be #unapologetic.” This partnership as well as the theme ‘unapologetic’ will also be included in the analysis of the problematic features of the SISI. Theories of sexual objectification will be applied based on the work of feminist scholars Sandra Bartky, Martha Nussbaum, Mary Jo Kane, and Iris Marion Young. References: Davis, Paul (2001). ‘Sexualization and Sexuality in Sport.’ Ethics in Sport. Morgan, W.J, Meier, K and Schneider A. J, Eds. Champaign IL: Human Kinetics, pp. 285-292. Nussbaum, Martha (1999). Sex and Social Justice. New York: Oxford University Press Young, I.M. (2005). On female body experience: Throwing like a girl and other essays.New York: Oxford University Press. Professional and Contact Information Charlene Weaving Associate Professor Human Kinetics Dept. St. Francis Xavier University. [email protected] 43 Junko Yamaguchi Title: Enhancing the cultural identity through the body-self unity in the Native American Canoe Journey Project Keywords: global society, performance, spirituality, invented tradition Abstract: My central concern is how the individual spiritual body-self experience transforms the collective cultural identity and to see how the traditional culture is invented to the new style of tradition in a global society. There is an intriguing Native American, Inter Tribal Canoe Journey Project on the West Coast of Washington State, which has about a 20 year-long history. On the West Coast, the Puget Sound [Salish Sea], and some of the British Columbia Nations, each tribe sets out on a Journey over three weeks; setting off with the tides and on a planned schedule. Over one hundred canoes with approximately one thousand pullers come from all over the coast and rivers paddle to the final host tribal Nations. The Canoe Journey Project among the inter tribes resembles the Dragon Boat Race in Southern Asia as well as in the East. In Asia competition holds the symbolic myth that the Dragon is a powerful spirit of water under an everyday religious Buddhist belief, and seeks blessings for a season blessed with an abundant harvest in the rice-producing district. In the Canoe Journey, on the contrary, there is no competitive match against a particular team, at this event. We see a kind of “invention of tradition”, in that tribal people promote ancestor respect to foster the Native Youth Leadership Program and enhance the Tribal Nation Identity as they connect the wisdom of the elders with the dreams of the younger generations. It is called the Healing Canoe Journey, and it is run with no drugs, alcohol, and no violence; some tribes even forbid suicide (which is very prevalent in Indian Nations). Nowadays the Nations’ Identities are accelerating in the West Coast of Washington State in that the project has been highly important part for their spiritual expression in their active lifestyles year by year since 1989, as we see there are thousands of spectators. The areas of Puget Sound of the State of Washington are more advanced globally, together with the internet-society. This raises the question of whether the canoe Journey Project is an “invented tradition” through the spiritual experience for the Nations’ Identities. Reference: 1. Metheny, E. (1968.1979). The Symbolic Power of Sport, Sport and the Body: A Philosophical Symposium, Lea & Febiger. 2. King, C. R. (Ed.). (2008) . Native Americans and Sport in North America : Other People's Games, London and New York: Routledge. Professional and Contact Information Junko Yamaguchi, Prof. Dr. Tsuda College, Japan [email protected] 44 Yang Zhang and Li Guisen Title: Positive Influences of Olympic Humanistic Ideas on the Development of Chinese Society Key words: Olympism, Confucianism, harmonious ideas, harmonious society Abstract: Different from normal sport games, the Olympic Games is a kind of social activity aiming to realize some ideal under the guidance of certain philosophy which is the Olympism. By studying and analyzing a large number of related materials and literatures, as well as the employment of questionnaires, this paper conducted an inductive analysis of the Olympic humanistic ideas and their promotion in the establishment of harmonious society in China. The essences of the Olympic humanistic ideas lie in the respect for humanity and in the philosophical thinking about life, which are mainly reflected in Olympism. It tries to facilitate human’s harmonious development through the combination and integration of sports and education so as to build a harmonious society that respects and protects dignity. As the essence of the Confucianism in ancient China and the mainstream ideology of Chinese traditional culture, harmony has profound influence on the country’s modern development. Both the Olympic humanistic ideas and China’s harmonious society ideal are essences of human thoughts. Although generated from different origins, they have many similarities in promoting the development of harmonious society. The successful holding of 2008 Beijing Olympic Games has integrated and interacted the two thoughts with each other that on one hand, the Olympics’ development in China has promoted its internationalization and diversification; on the other hand and more importantly, the Olympic humanistic ideas have enriched the ideology of harmonious society, and provided a new approach to realize it. References International Olympic Committee. “Olympic Charter”. <http://www.olympic.org/documents/olympic_charter_en.pdf>. Segrave, Jeffrey. Olympism. Illinois: Human Kinetics, 1981. The Analects of Confucius. Annotated by Zhang Yanying. Beijing: Zhonghua Book Company, 2006. Professional and Contact Information Zhang Yang Lecturer Capital Institute of Physical Education [email protected] Li Guisen Lecturer China Youth University for Political Sciences [email protected] 45 Ana Zimmerman and Soraia Chung Saura Title: Body, environment and adventure: beyond adrenaline Key words: adventure, perception, human movement, experience, embodiment. Abstract: The purpose of this paper is to investigate human spatiality, and perception in general, with the experience of adventure sports as background. These activities especially highlight our strong relationship with the world considering the specific way the environment participates in their development. It is the presence of instability and risk that makes them what they are. More than a different range of corporeal techniques, adventure sports can teach us a way of interrogating and looking at the world. They require a peculiar sensibility that allows our body to experience the environment by silencing knowledge in favour of a corporeal wisdom. The word “adrenaline”, metaphors, or interjections are frequently used by adventurers to summarize their experiences indicating a corporeal engagement that is better described than explained. This paper explores the notions of perception, experience and spatiality, considering mainly the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty and Bachelard and some counterpoints on Deleuze’s aesthetic. Alternative body practices indicate the possibility we have to build up different ways of inhabiting the world. References: Bachelard, G. A Poética do Espaço. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2008. Bachelard, G. A Poética do Devaneio. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 1988. Deleuze, G; Guattari, F. 1991. Qu'est-ce que la philosophie? Paris: Les éditions de minuit. Merleau-Ponty, M. 2002. Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1964. Signs. Northwestern University Press: Evanston, Illinois. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1974. The prose of the world. London: Heinemann Educational. Professional and Contact Information Ana Zimmermann Assistant Professor School of Physical Education and Sport University of São Paulo Brazil [email protected] Soraia Chung Saura – Assistant Professor School of Physical Education and Sport University of São Paulo Brazil [email protected] 46 ABSTRACTS IN PORTUGUESE & SPANISH RESUMOS EM PORTUGUES & ESPAÑOL Asociación Latina de Filosofía del Deporte Associação Latina de Filosofia do Desporto 47 Carlos Alberto de Andrade Coelho Filho Título: O malhar como metáfora da exercitação física Palavras-chave: exercício físico, malhar, filosofia da linguagem Resumo: No Brasil, a palavra malhar passa a ser utilizada como metáfora da exercitação física, e ganha força simultaneamente aos programas televisivos (novelas e humorísticos) e às canções que passam a utilizá-la como tema, com grande sucesso. Em 1983, por exemplo, o compositor Marcos Valle gravou o LP “Marcos Valle”, contendo canções de sua autoria, dentre as quais “Estrelar” (cujo single vendeu cerca de 90 mil cópias, quase alcançando um Disco de Ouro), que diz em um trecho: “Tem que correr, tem que suar, tem que malhar...”. Considere-se aqui, obviamente, o status midiático, ou o poder de persuasão midiático, e sua relação com a linguagem. Nesse sentido, importa notar que a metáfora tem sua historicidade; delineia-se em um campo enunciativo onde adquire lugar e status, que lhe apresenta relações com o passado e lhe descortina um futuro eventual. Como diz Ricoeur, a metáfora é sempre portadora de uma significação emergente conferida por alguns contextos específicos, e pode ser considerada uma criação linguística, ou, mais precisamente, uma inovação semântica. Contudo, se ela passa a ser adotada por uma parte importante da comunidade linguística, pode, por sua vez, tornar-se uma significação usual e juntar-se à polissemia das entidades lexicais, código ou sistema. Nesse último estágio, quando o efeito de sentido a que chamamos metáfora alcançar a mudança de sentido que aumenta a polissemia, nos termos de Ricoeur, a metáfora deixará de ser metáfora viva e passará a ser metáfora morta. Com efeito, duas constatações associadas à palavra malhar merecem destaque: (1) etimologicamente, ela tem em si a ideia de mancha (mácula), de bater, contundir e dar pancada, de castigar o corpo, de zombar e escarnecer; (2) o significado “fazer ginástica ou exercício físico para fortalecer os músculos e manter a linha” só passa a figurar em dicionários conceituais (enciclopédicos) a partir do final dos anos 1990. Portanto, ainda que o corpo que “malha” possa remeter para a imagem de um corpo dotado de supervitalidade, ou o ato de “malhar” representar um meio de resistência às diferentes formas de decadência física, a apropriação social da palavra malhar para caracterizar a prática do exercício físico parece também não escapar ao sentido de castigar o corpo, isto é, o de violência contra uma matéria que deve ser moldada a golpes. Apontamos, então, para um movimento que parece fornecer subsídios para a reflexão vinculada, por exemplo, à diminuição preocupante do nível de atividade física da população. Nesse diapasão, tendo por base o pensamento de Ricoeur, nossa questão se coloca para o campo da Filosofia do Esporte: uma atividade de análise e reflexão sobre a utilização da palavra malhar como metáfora da exercitação física pode contribuir para uma melhor compreensão dessa prática e/ou do fazer corporal esportivo? Referências: Coelho Filho C A A (2007). Metamorfose de um corpo “andarilho”: busca e reencontro do “algo” melhor. São Paulo: Casa do Psicólogo. Gregolin M R V (2004). O enunciado e o arquivo: Foucault (entre)vistas. In: Foucault e os domínios da linguagem: discurso, poder, subjetividade. Vanice Sargentini, Pedro Navarro-Barbosa (Orgs.). São Carlos: Claraluz, 23-96. Ricoeur P (2011). Escritos e conferências 2: hermenêutica. São Paulo: Loyola. Malhar (2014). [Brasil, Informal] Fazer ginástica ou exercício físico para fortalecer os músculos e manter a linha. In: Dicionário Priberam da Língua Portuguesa. Recuperado em 25 de março, 2014, de http://www.priberam.pt/dlpo/malhar Teixeira F L S, Caminha I O (2010). A supervitalidade como forma de poder: um olhar a partir das academias de ginástica. Revista Movimento, 16 (03): 203-220. 48 Santos S F, Salles A D (2009). Antropologia de uma academia de musculação: um olhar sobre o corpo e um espaço de representação social. Revista Brasileira de Educação Física e Esporte, 23 (02): 87-102. Hansen R, Vaz A F (2004). Treino, culto e embelezamento do corpo: um estudo em academias de ginástica e musculação. Revista Brasileira de Ciências do Esporte, 26 (01): 135-152. Organización Panamericana de la Salud (2006). Impulso panamericano en favor de una dieta saludable y actividad física. Recuperado em 31 de janeiro, 2012, de http://www.paho.org/Spanish/DD/PIN/ps060228.htm#Top Ricoeur P (1975). La métaphore vive. Paris: Le Seuil, 1975. Instituição Carlos Alberto de Andrade Coelho Filho Universidade Federal de Juiz de Fora [email protected] 49 Marco Antonio Oliveira de Azevedo Título: Novamente, sobre jogos e paradoxos Palavras-chave: conceito de jogo, paradoxos, Bernard Suits, grasshopper, Aurel Kolnai Resumo: Um dos debates mais interessantes sobre a natureza do jogo foi encenado pelos filósofos Aurel Kolnai e Bernard Suits. Num artigo intitulado "Games and Aims", de 1965, e publicado no volume 66 da Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Kolnai sustentou que jogos competitivos são empreendimentos essencialmente paradoxais. Jogos, entendidos como atividades competitivas promovidas em mútuo acordo sob os limites estabelecidos por um conjunto definido de regras e um contrato explícito, exibiriam o seguinte paradoxo interno: a fim de que o jogo aconteça, os jogadores precisam concordar amigavelmente em agir como parceiros, para, logo a seguir, esforçarem-se para derrotar um ao outro. Em outras palavra, os parceiros agem como antagonistas; mas ambos precisam almejar o objetivo mútuo de jogar o jogo. Juntos colaboram para que, separadamente, cada um tenta vencer o outro; mas isso também implica esforçar-se para que o outro não alcance o objetivo de vencer o jogo. Bernard Suits reagiu a isso dando ao personagem principal de seu The Grasshopper a tarefa de encaminhar uma resposta adequada (Suits, 1978, p. 74-81). Se jogos competitivos forem empreendimentos paradoxais, então eles seriam presumivelmente indefiníveis—o que representaria um golpe fatal ao objetivo de Suits de mostrar que é possível dar uma definição de "jogo" de forma completamente satisfatória. Suits esforça-se para demonstrar que jogos não envolvem paradoxos. Cooperar para jogar e desejar vencer não podem e não são objetivos contraditórios. Mas ao mesmo tempo em que recusa a ideia de que, em competições, os jogadores poderiam assumir uma postura volitiva exótica (a atitude que consistiria em atuar com objetivos contraditórios), Suits sugere algumas situações que fariam de jogos competitivos empreendimentos problemáticos. Tais situações envolveriam os seguintes paradoxos: o paradoxo do vitorioso relutante, o paradoxo da benignidade infinita, o paradoxo do vencedor compulsivo e o paradoxo do jogador procrastinador. Após apresentar essas situações, Suits sugere que o que caracteriza um jogo é justamente o fato de tratar-se de um empreendimento que evita esses paradoxos. "Jogos", diz Suits, "são o tipo de coisa na qual há a possibilidade, de fato, o perigo, de que esse paradoxo ocorra" (Suits, 1978, p. 79); e um bom jogo seria justamente o tipo de atividade que evitaria o "paradoxo". Meu objetivo nesta comunicação é duplo. Primeiro, pretendo retomar o debate, buscando tornar clara a divergência original entre Kolnai e Suits. Segundo, pretendo explorar uma ideia proposta por Suits, a saber, de que jogos são empreendimentos artificiais cujos objetivos "autotélicos" (seguindo o jargão de Kolnai) somente conduzem a situações paradoxais caso seus jogadores evitem (ou não se disponham voluntariamente a) alcançá-los. Evitar o paradoxo também parece explicar por que práticas como o doping (entre outras práticas) são rejeitadas em uma competição justa. Ao final, pretendo retomar os argumentos em defesa de que a passagem do jogo ao esporte envolve a solução a um problema que surge no instante em que competições são levadas a sério pelos jogadores. Jogos não poderiam ser empreendimentos sérios, a menos que se institucionalizem como práticas sociais estáveis. Instituição Marco Antonio Oliveira de Azevedo Universidade do Vale do Rio dos Sinos [email protected] 50 Jorge Olímpio Bento y Helena Cristina Baguinho Bento Título: Desporto e valores: uma aliança natural carecida de renovação Resumo: Uma viagem às fontes matriciais do desporto (‘arété’, cultura e paideia gregas) e às luzes da sua renovação (Modernidade, Humanismo e Iluminismo) revela-nos que ele nasceu e cresceu de uma aliança natural com fins, normativos, princípios, referenciais e símbolos axiológicos, éticos e estéticos. Nesta conformidade à elaboração deste texto presidem os seguintes objetivos: • ‘Recordar’ e revisitar a matriz ‘artística’ do desporto. • Apelar à urgência de remissão discursiva e prática do ideário desportivo. • Advertir para desvios e perigos da mentalidade fabricadora e utilitária, de uma racionalidade científica, sem abertura para inquietudes éticas. • Acordar a necessidade de renovar os olhares filosóficos e pedagógicos sobre o desporto. • Desatar as energias interiores de cada um e fazer sonhar com novos céus e nova terra. O foco principal desta reflexão visa chamar a atenção para o facto de que o desporto (como espetáculo, nomeadamente o futebol) está a esquecer a sua idiossincrasia, a ser capturado pelo pragmatismo e utilitarismo, pelos tentáculos do polvo do mercado e pela ‘civilização do espetáculo’, correndo o risco de se afastar do estádio grego e abeirar do circo romano, de se divorciar da arété e paideia gregas, da cultura humanista e iluminista. O mesmo se passa na educação, inclusive na universidade, bem como no contexto sóciocultural. Por isso o olhar sobre o desporto implica um olhar sobre a conjuntura e reprova a indiferença face ao que nela acontece. Perante este inquietante panorama impõe-se cumprir a obrigação de resistir e sobreviver, deitando mãos ao arrimo da filosofia. Instituição Jorge Olímpio Bento Universidade do Porto [email protected] Helena Cristina Baguinho Bento Universidade do Porto 51 Daniel G. Campos Título: Sentimentalismo filosófico y afición al fútbol latinoamericano Palavras-chave: ética, deporte, razón, sentimiento Resumo: En El fútbol a sol y sombra, Eduardo Galeano dice no ser más “que un mendigo del buen fútbol. Voy por el mundo sombrero en mano, y en los estadios suplico: —Una linda jugadita, por amor de Dios. Y cuando el buen fútbol ocurre, agradezco el milagro sin que me importe un rábano cuál es el club o el país que me lo ofrece” (2002, p. 1). El autor de la presente ponencia, sin embargo, confiesa que en la Copa del Mundo FIFA sí le importa cuál país le ofrece sus triunfos. Siempre apoya a los equipos latinoamericanos. De hecho, apoya al archirrival latinoamericano de su propio país contra selecciones de cualquier otra región, y prefiere que gane, aunque el otro equipo juegue “mejor” o “más bonito”. No se trata de un regionalismo similar al nacionalismo patriótico defendido por Dixon (2000), sino más bien de un sentimiento de solidaridad con sociedades con las que siente afinidad. En términos normativos, la declaración de Galeano podría sugerir un ideal lógico-estético al que el buen aficionado al fútbol debería aspirar. Se debería apoyar al “mejor” fútbol en el sentido de la actuación deportiva que mejor resuelva, con base en habilidades cultivadas y tácticas lícitas, los problemas específicos que plantea el fútbol. Además, se debería apoyar al fútbol estéticamente más bello, de acuerdo con ideales de belleza defendibles. Sin embargo, este ideal nos pide que ignoremos nuestros sentimientos en pos de ideales teóricos. En esta presentación, por el contrario, se intentará defender un sentimentalismo razonable con base en la filosofía de Charles Peirce. Según Peirce, el “sentimentalismo” es la doctrina filosófica de que debemos otorgar profundo respeto a los juicios naturales del corazón sensible (1893). Además, Peirce argumenta que mientras en asuntos teóricos debe regir el razonamiento lógico, aunque ayudado por el sentimiento instintivo para conjeturar, en asuntos prácticos de importancia vital debe regir el sentimiento aunque criticado por la razón reflexiva (1898). Por “sentimiento” no se entiende sensación ni emoción momentánea sino un hábito—disposición para la acción—de fuerte carga afectiva que sirve para guiar las acciones vitales. Por ende, el “sentimentalismo” no es un “emotivismo” como el criticado por Mumford (2012). Para Peirce, la sabiduría que conduce al buen vivir consiste en distinguir cuando debe primar la razón asistida por el sentimiento en asuntos teóricos y cuando debe primar el sentimiento asistido por la razón en asuntos de importancia vital. Tal sabiduría no incurre en dicotomías, sino que busca dar el énfasis correcto en los continuos teoría-práctica, razón-sentimiento. Se argumentará que la afición al fútbol es un asunto de importancia vital, por involucrar vínculos afectivos, relaciones con personas, lugares y comunidades, y fines relacionados al buen vivir. En tales asuntos, sentimientos morales—e.g. hábitos de cooperación, mutuo apoyo y celebración compartida—deben guiar nuestras acciones. Éstos sugieren que es razonablemente sensible solidarizarnos, a través de la práctica del fútbol, con aquellos que nos son más afines socioculturalmente. Sin embargo, esta disposición afectiva no debe llevarnos a la animosidad contra miembros de otros grupos sociales, culturales, y demás, violando la disposición hacia la solidaridad e inclusión. Para prevenir tales actitudes, la reflexión crítica y una orientación hacia la “sim-patía” (“el sentir junto con otros”) inclusiva deben controlar a los sentimientos de solidaridad socio-cultural para que no viren anti-páticos hacia los demás. `En términos concretos de afición al fútbol, mi hipótesis es que el sentimiento de solidaridad sociocultural puede ser razonable—mesurado, capaz de reconocer superioridad del rival sin identificarse ni alegrarse por él, y demás. Sin embargo, cuando este tipo de solidaridad se olvida de la sim-patía inclusiva, puede llevar al insulto, la agresión, e incluso el odio. Se requieren entonces la crítica 52 razonable y la revitalización sim-pática. Pero no hay porqué obligarse, por razones abstractas de una teoría del deporte, a apoyar el “mejor” fútbol o el “más bello”, lo juegue quien lo juegue. Referências: Dixon, Nicholas. 2000. “A Justification of Moderate Patriotism in Sport.” En Values in Sport: Elitism, Nationalism, Gender Equality, and the Scientific Manufacturing of Winners. Eds. T. Tannsjo and C. Tamburrini. New York: E&FN Spon. Mumford, Stephen. 2012. Watching Sport: Aesthetics, Ethics and Emotion. New York: Routledge. Galeano, Eduardo. 2002. El fútbol a sol y sombra. Montevideo: Ediciones del Chanchito. Peirce, Charles S. (1893) 1992. “Evolutionary Love.” En The Essential Peirce, Vol. 1. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Peirce, Charles S. (1898) 1992. “Philosophy and the Conduct of Life”. En Reasoning and the Logic of Things. Ed. K.L. Ketner. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Instituição Daniel G. Campos Brooklyn College – City University of New York [email protected] 53 Rebeca Cardozo Coelho, Lev Kreft y Teresa Lacerda Título: A experiência estética do atleta da seleção portuguesa de taekwondo Palavras-chave: experiência estética, atleta, taekwondo, poomsae, combate Resumo: Conhecimento com um vasto potencial ainda por explorar, a estética do desporto e, mais especificamente, a estética dos desportos de combate, como o Taekwondo, desperta um interesse cada vez maior no domínio das ciências do desporto. O presente estudo, uma tese de doutoramento, buscou a compreensão da experiência estética vivenciada por atletas séniores da Seleção Portuguesa de Taekwondo, na prática da poomsae e do combate. Partiu-se da literatura sobre estética geral, sobre estética do desporto e sobre Taekwondo, da consideração das peculiaridades do objeto e da experiência pessoal. A experiência estética é mais magnificente do que uma experiência simplesmente (Lacerda, 2004), caracteriza-se pelo conteúdo do fenómeno da cognição que se apresenta na nossa perceção, assim como pelo valor desta experiência, que é singular (Matravers, 2003; Huisman, 2008; Kant, 2010). Estas experiências podem ser valiosas de diversas maneiras para aqueles que as vivenciam (Iseminger, 2003), e não existem apenas na sensibilidade do indivíduo, residem também na imaginação (Schiller, 1991; Kant, 2010), pelo que o atleta pode saborear o gozo das qualidades estéticas que consegue criar na prática desportiva. A literatura evidenciou que no Taekwondo a tranquila beleza das suas formas e movimentos manifesta-se tanto na realização das ações que configuram a performance, quanto no controlo das emoções que fluem (Il-hyeok, 2000). O Taekwondo apresentou-se também como sendo um jogo, no qual coexiste o prazer de vencer o adversário real ou imaginado, de obter uma vitória durante um combate árduo. O atleta, em alguns momentos, demonstra ser um indivíduo destemido e audaz, capaz de se realizar também pelo risco implicado no jogo. Para que se pudesse aceder de modo aprofundado ao ponto de vista dos atletas, e com o propósito de descrever e interpretar a experiência estética por eles vivenciada, realizaram-se entrevistas. Deste modo, a pesquisa, de natureza qualitativa com uma abordagem fenomenológica, assumiu um carácter descritivo e exploratório. O discurso de 22 atletas foi captado em entrevistas semiestruturadas e a informação recolhida foi tratada por meio da análise de conteúdo. Relativamente aos atletas de poomsae foi manifesto que os elementos técnica, tática/jogo, afetividade/gosto, agressividade, transcendência/superação e kihap (grito), são significativos para a compreensão da experiência estética destes indivíduos. Já em relação aos atletas de combate foi possível perceber que os elementos técnica, tática/jogo, afetividade/gosto, agressividade, risco, superação, vitória e kihap (grito), se apresentaram como os mais significativos para o entendimento da experiência estética neste contexto. Esses elementos compõem a prática e se transformam em momentos expressivos, fontes de prazer. A análise e a interpretação dessas informações, permitiu concluir, portanto, que o atleta de Taekwondo, a partir da busca pela execução de forma perfeita das técnicas e da tática, com o apoio constante dos seus companheiros, adotando uma postura agressiva/assertiva, ultrapassando situações arriscadas, e em alguns momentos com a exteriorização da sua energia interior através do kihap, superando limites, vencendo, é capaz de aceder a experiências harmoniosas, belas, lúdicas, afetivas, isto é, experiências estéticas. Referências: Huisman, D. (2008). A estética. Lisboa: Edições 70. Il-hyeok, L. (2000). Taekwondo's Philosophy and Aesthetics. Koreana, Seoul 14(4), 8-15. Iseminger, G. (2003). Aesthetic Experience. In Levinson, J. (2003). The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Oxford: University Press, 99-116. 54 Kant, I. (2010). Crítica da Faculdade do Juízo. Rio de Janeiro: Forense Universitária. Kreft, L. (2012). Sport as a drama. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, Champaing, 39(2), 219-234. Lacerda, T. de O. (2004). Acerca da natureza da experiência estética desencadeada pelo encontro com o Desporto e do seu contributo para a educação estética do ser humano. In Lebre, E. & Bento, J. (Ed.). Professor de Educação Física: ofícios da profissão. Porto: FCDEF-UP, 301-307. Matravers, D. (2003). The aesthetic experience. British Journal of Aesthetics, 43(2), 158-174. Schiller, F. (1991). Cartas sobre a educação estética da humanidade. São Paulo: EPU. Instituição Rebeca Cardozo Coelho Universidade do Porto [email protected] Lev Kreft University of Ljubljana [email protected] Teresa Lacerda Universidade do Porto [email protected] 55 Eduardo Klein Carmona, Alberto de Oliveira Monteiro y Janice Zarpellon Mazo Título: Esporte paralímpico: uma reflexão acerca dos valores Palavras-chave: axiologia, valores, Olimpismo, movimento Paralímpico Resumo: O esporte é uma forma de linguagem universal produzida e reproduzida por, praticamente, todos os povos, grupos, etnias e/ou culturas do planeta, e que, ao mesmo tempo, é capaz de manifestar diversos valores sociais e humanos. Valor pode ser entendido como uma espécie de crença consensual coletiva de duração estável que oferece ou dá sentido e significado às relações sociais e culturais. Cabe ressaltar que os valores são uma experiência inevitável, tendo sua forma de materialização e expressão através comportamentos, como em atitudes e em gestos. Na filosofia, os valores são estudados por uma vertente denominada axiologia. Já nas ciências do esporte e da educação física, temos o olimpismo enquanto uma espécie filosofia que enaltece as qualidades do corpo, espírito e mente através do esporte, associado a valores educacionais e éticos universais. Desta forma, aportados pela axiologia (o estudo dos valores) e pela filosofia do olimpismo, buscamos trazer uma reflexão acerca dos valores escolhidos pelo International Paralympic Committee (IPC) para representar o movimento paralímpico e os Jogos Paralímpicos, os quais são: a determinação, a coragem, a inspiração e a igualdade. Cabe mencionar que esses valores se diferem dos valores olímpicos: excelência, respeito e amizade. Os valores estabelecidos pelos IPC foram significados de modo particular para o movimento paralímpico, sendo: a determinação para superar obstáculos e vencer a adversidade; a coragem para realizar o inesperado, para além das expectativas; a inspiração para entusiasmar e proporcionar intensa afeição pessoal; além da igualdade enquanto um mecanismo para o esporte paralímpico atuar como um agente de mudança atitudinal no combate da discriminação em relação às pessoas com deficiência. Os valores paralímpicos buscam representar as potencialidades das pessoas com deficiência, como, também, sensibilizar as pessoas sem deficiência para com essas outras pessoas, não através de um olhar de piedade, mas, sim, de respeito e admiração. Instituição Eduardo Klein Carmona Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] Alberto de Oliveira Monteiro Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul Janice Zarpellon Mazo Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul 56 Michelle Carreirão Gonçalves y Alexandre Fernandez Vaz Título: Esporte e estética: Representações da forma de jogo no rúgbi feminino Palavras-chave: esporte, estética, técnica, mimese, rúgbi Resumo: O presente trabalho se propõe a debater relações entre estética e esporte, analisando o fenômeno esportivo como um dos que mais proporciona elevado prazer e beleza no contemporâneo. Perguntamos pelas representações estéticas do esporte, deslocando o olhar dos espectadores para os praticantes, numa tentativa de mais bem entender a questão por um ângulo distinto daquele comumente encontrado na literatura, em que é analisada a partir da recepção. Para tanto, tomamos como fonte para pesquisa uma equipe de rúgbi feminina da cidade de Florianópolis/SC (Brasil), escolha feita de forma um tanto exploratória, considerando que pouco ainda se conhece da modalidade no Brasil, tanto por espectadores, quanto por acadêmicos. Foi realizado um conjunto de observações do cotidiano do time, bem como 4 entrevistas semiestruturadas com jogadoras que compõem o grupo, escolhidas por fazerem também parte do selecionado nacional. Somado a esse material, tem-se observações-piloto junto a um clube de rúgbi da cidade de La Plata/Argentina, além de material coletado durante evento da Confederação Brasileira de Rugby em 2011, realizado em São Paulo, cujos fins eram o selecionamento de jogadoras para a equipe nacional. No que concerne ao referencial teórico que ofereceu embasamento à pesquisa, trabalhamos com autores como Wolfgang Welsch (com seus argumentos que reivindicam o estatuto de arte ao esporte), Gunter Gebauer (sobre as relações entre esporte e mimese), Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht (no que diz respeito ao lugar privilegiado do esporte no âmbito da estética da presença) e José Miguel Wisnik (que toma o futebol como exemplo mais bem acabado de desfrute estético no campo esportivo, pensando-o no diálogo com a literatura). Somado a isso, buscamos também na Teoria Estética de Theodor W. Adorno conceitos que nos ajudaram a mais bem compreender o fenômeno, como matéria, material e forma, além de indicações sobre as relações entre mimese e técnica na construção da obra de arte. Os resultados indicam: 1) que os cuidados com o corpo compõem o quadro de preocupações das praticantes dessa modalidade, na medida em que este se coloca como matéria para a obra esportiva; 2) que os gestos técnicos da modalidade são fundamentais para a produção de forma, constituindo-se como material da obra; 3) que a forma de jogo preferida pelas jogadoras relaciona-se com aquilo que chamam de jogo aberto, que é veloz, ofensivo e malandro; 4) que a criação da obra esportiva parece aproximar-se com a da obra de arte, na medida em que ambas conjugam espírito e natureza, técnica e mimese, na elaboração do belo. Referências: ADORNO, T.W. Teoria Estética. Lisboa: Edições 70, 2008. GEBAUER, G. Ästhetische Erfahrung der Praxis: das Mimetische im Sport. In: KÖNIG, E.; LUTZ, R. (Orgs.). Bewegungskulturen: Ansätze zu einer kritischen Anthropologie des Körpers. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, 1995. p. 189 - 198. GUMBRECHT, H.U. Elogio da beleza atlética. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras, 2007. Instituição Michelle Carreirão Gonçalves Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais [email protected] Alexandre Fernandez Vaz Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina [email protected] 57 Alberto Carrio Título: Especificidad del deporte y control del pasaporte biológico Palavras-chave: especificidad del deporte, tratado de Lisboa, pasaporte biológico, derechos fundamentales Resumo: El Tratado de Lisboa ha reconocido la especificidad del deporte a partir de la consideración de cinco funciones básicas de toda actividad deportiva, a saber: educación, salud pública, función social, recreativa y cultural. Este reconocimiento supone un cambio importante en la política del deporte europeo que posibilita un control creciente de las reglas de las competiciones y de la actividad de las organizaciones deportivas. En este artículo pretendo analizar i) la paradójica consecuencia del reconocimiento de la especificidad del deporte por las instituciones europeas, y, ii) la dudosa utilidad este reconocimiento a partir de la consideración conjunta de las funciones básicas y los valores fundamentales del deporte . En relación con el primer apartado, no deja de resultar irónico que se haga descansar el reconocimiento de especificidad del deporte en los valores fundamentales del deporte cuando sus promotores probablemente perseguían lo contrario: la exención de la legislación europea a un floreciente ámbito económico. Pero es el segundo apartado el que resulta más sorprendente dado que puede terminar alcanzando justo el objetivo contrario al que inicialmente se perseguía. Es decir, con la finalidad de preservar el Fair Play, como valor fundamental del deporte tal y como lo reconoce el Tratado de Lisboa, las Federaciones deportivas someten a los atletas a controles antidopaje que difícilmente pueden ser avalados por la Carta de Derechos europea debido a la lesión de ciertos derechos fundamentales básicos. Se da así la paradoja de que el reconocimiento de la especificidad del Deporte por el Tratado de la Unión termine por avalar la negativa de los deportistas a someterse a los estrictos controles de dopaje a los que hasta ahora los sujetaba la WADA de acuerdo con las respectivas federaciones deportivas. Referências: LOLAND, S., Fair Play in Sport. A moral norm System. London, Routledge, 2002. Parrish, R, et al, The Lisbon Treaty and EU sports policy: study. Brussels, European Parliament. Instituição Alberto Carrio Universitat Pompeu Fabra [email protected] 58 Nilzalina Silva Chaparro, Mara Regina Rosa Ribeiro, Paulo Cunha e Silva y Teresa Lacerda Título: Olhar sensível: afeto e solidariedade presentes no brincar da criança hospitalizada Palavras-chave: olhar sensível, estética, brincar, criança hospitalizada Resumo: O trabalho ora apresentado constituiu resultado parcial da tese de doutorado intitulada “O corpo doente pode ser estético? Estudo interpretativo a partir da dimensão da criança hospitalizada” (Chaparro, 2013), sendo o mesmo guiado pelo olhar do lúdico e da estética. Nesse sentido, o brincar da criança hospitalizada exigiu que se fizesse leitura de múltiplos sentimentos expressos e daí sua aproximação com a ciência sensitiva de Baumgarten, que ruma em direção oposta à da logica, articulando-se, antes, com a sensibilidade. A afetividade e a solidariedade foram algumas das características mostradas no estudo. Os gestos afetivos revelados pelos profissionais estiveram ligados a: respeito pela individualidade da criança, recepcionar as crianças com sorriso, elogiar suas ações, mostrar-se alegre e bonita, abraços, beijos, uso de jaleco com motivos infantis e levar roupas das bonecas para lavar em casa. A solidariedade se mostrou sob a forma de uma rede articulada para o brincar acontecer: profissionais de enfermagem procuravam conciliar a administração da medicação com o tempo de brincar, professoras criavam meios para a criança brincar na cama e decodificavam símbolos expressos pelas crianças e ainda o “estar junto para brincar”. As características subjectivas presentes no brincar, das quais se percebeu decorrer uma forte carga emotiva, constituíram, deste modo, um dos indicadores da presença da estética no brincar da criança hospitalizada. De facto, ficou explícito que a comoção desencadeada pelo brincar possuía traços da estética entendida por Maffesoli (2005, p. 8) como “vibrar em comum, sentir em uníssono, experimentar coletivamente, tudo o que permite a cada um, movido pelo ideal comunitário, sentir-se daqui e em casa neste mundo”. Na realidade a força atrativa do brincar residia nessa vontade de fazer acontecer e “experimentar junto”, daí que os profissionais e as crianças lançavam mão de mecanismos sensíveis, no caso a afetividade e a solidariedade, para tornar a vontade comum real. Os gestos afetivos somados aos solidários serviram de elementos estruturantes ao olhar sensível dos profissionais e crianças. A indissociabilidade desses aspectos apresentados nos deu sustentação para denominá-los de olhar estético, na mesma perspectiva de Pereira (2006, p. 290) que descreve esse olhar como um “olhar amoroso, uma atitude da alma, o que implica uma atitude mais radical da consciência perante a facticidade, a capacidade de poetizar, a capacidade de experienciar sentimentos, para nos dar a verdadeira realidade, a mais profunda, a mais alta e a mais rica.” Referências: Chaparro, N. S. (2013). O CORPO DOENTE PODE SER ESTÉTICO? ESTUDO INTERPRETATIVO A PARTIR DA DIMENSÃO LÚDICA EM CRIANÇAS HOSPITALIZADAS. Porto: N. S. Chaparro. Dissertação de Doutoramento Apresentada à Faculdade de Desporto da Universidade do Porto. Mafessoli. M. (2005). O mistério da conjunção (J. M. Silva trad.), Porto Alegre. Sulina. Pereira, P. C. (2006). Do sentir e do pensar. Edições Afrontamento, Porto. 59 Instituição Nilzalina Silva Chaparro Universidade Federal de Mato Grosso [email protected] Mara Regina Rosa Universidade Federal de Mato Grosso [email protected] Ribeiro, Paulo Cunha e Silva Universidade do Porto [email protected] Teresa Lacerda Universidade do Porto [email protected] 60 Soraia Chung Saura y Ana Cristina Zimmermann Título: O jogo e a festa, o tempo e o movimento Palavras-chave: temporalidade, movimentar-se, celebração Resumo: O objetivo deste estudo é explorar a noção de temporalidade, considerando a experiência em esportes, jogos e danças, examinando especialmente a presença da repetição versus novidade. Movimentos expressivos, como jogos e danças, nos permitem reconhecer uma experiência que não é necessariamente associada ao tempo cronológico, bem relatada por esportistas e dançarinos. O jogo, a dança, o esporte de um modo geral nos mostram como elaboramos nossa temporalidade em função de uma relação dialógica que se estabelece sobretudo a partir de nossa corporalidade. Atletas, quando em campo, descrevem uma percepção de organicidade fortemente associados à experiência do tempo. Também descrevem, em uma relação mais ampla com os eventos esportivos, a integração temporal por meio da ritmidade cíclica. De qualquer maneira, todas as experiências de temporalidade apontam para uma forma de habitar o tempo que exige o estabelecimento de uma relação e a elaboração de novos sentidos e significados. O jogo, a dança, o esporte nos mostram como elaboramos nossa temporalidade em função de uma relação dialógica e imagética. A experiência temporal revela um saber elaborado no corpo, durante o movimento do jogo e na ocorrência dos festivais anuais. A noção de temporalidade é trabalhada por Merleau-Ponty ao descrever a noção de tempo vivido associado a nossa presença como um “ser no mundo”. Neste sentido, o tempo vivido é o espaço temporalizado que permanece como um horizonte para nós. Gadamer, por sua vez, ao tratar da estrutura temporal da festa, se detém na noção de “celebrar” como um modo específico de nossa conduta no qual também não é possível identificar a presença de uma sequência de momentos. Trata-se do tempo vivenciado. Reconhecer estas formas de elaboração de nossa temporalidade pode auxiliar a compreender nossa absorção, participação e formas de antecipação, em certas experiências que respeitam a corporeidade presente na elaboração da temporalidade humana. Referências: BACHELARD, G. A Poética do Espaço. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2008. BACHELARD, G. A Poética do Devaneio. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 1988. GADAMER, H-G. A atualidade do belo: a arte como jogo símbolo e festa. Rio de Janeiro: Tempo Brasileiro 1985. GIL, J. Movimento total: o corpo e a dança. Lisboa: Relógio d‟água, 2001. MERLEAU-PONTY, M. Fenomenologia da percepção. São Paulo: Martins Fontes,1994. Instituição Soraia Chung Saura Universidade de São Paulo [email protected] Ana Zimmermann Universidade de São Paulo [email protected] 61 Anderson da Cunha Baía y Andrea Moreno Título: O papel do esporte no projeto formador das Associações Cristãs de Moços no Brasil (1920-1929) Palavras-chave: formação, esporte, história, Associação Cristã de Moços Resumo: Este estudo aborda o projeto de formação física da Associação Cristã de Moços (ACM) no Brasil, especialmente no que tange a presença do esporte na formação dos associados. A ACM foi criada na Inglaterra em 1844 e implantada no Brasil em 1893 por meio do norte-americano Myron Augusto Clark, cumprindo uma missão da sede da instituição de Nova Iorque em ampliar seu campo de atuação além das fronteiras dos Estados Unidos. Seu propósito nas diferentes regiões do mundo, segundo as bases de Paris – documento norteador das ações da instituição – era promover o desenvolvimento do caráter “cristão”, a “utilidade” dos seus membros e promover o “bem físico”, “intelectual”, “social” e “espiritual” dos moços. A partir do entendimento da existência de um investimento na formação física do associado, temos como propósito, nesse estudo, compreender o papel do esporte no projeto formador da Associação Cristã de Moços, no período de 1920 a 1929. As fontes mobilizadas foram: revista “Mocidade” e jornal “O Apóstolo”, jornal “O Puritano”; e documentos institucionais – panfletos, cartilhas, estatutos e atas. No projeto da ACM, no Brasil, aliada à formação intelectual e moral-religiosa estava o exercício físico – especialmente realizado por meio da ginástica e dos esportes. Havia um investimento da instituição no país na constituição de um ethos esportivo, salientando a importância das práticas esportivas na formação dos associados. Se, desde as origens das diferentes Associações Cristãs de Moços no país estava explicita a preocupação com a promoção do “bem physico” do sócio, a intensificação das ações do Departamento Físico somente foi percebida no início da década de 1920. O esporte foi utilizado, nesse momento, para sustentar o discurso institucional da formação de um corpo viril, forte (mas sem exageros de hipertrofia), saudável, eficiente, preparado para o trabalho, passível de controlar as vontades, recatado e ainda formado a partir dos predicados morais que conduziam os ensinamentos cristãos. Afinal, o corpo era também lugar da moral, da religião e do aprendizado. O corpo deveria, portanto, ser tratado como tal. Uma alimentação adequada, as formas de comportar e agir e as orientações de como deveria ser a atuação do esportista nos momentos de competições e póscompetição eram elementos que conduziam a uma “reforma dos costumes” nos hábitos corporais dos brasileiros. Essas ideias integraram um debate que, em grande parte, foi incorporado ao discurso acmista brasileiro por meio de um conjunto de textos escritos e traduzidos pelo missionário norteamericano que atuou em ACMs brasileiras, H. J. Sims. Esse missionário e outros sujeitos formados pela ACM participaram do debate acerca da escolarização do esporte em várias regiões do país. Assim, ao construir um projeto de formação física para os sócios, a Associação Cristã de Moços contribuiu na conformação da Educação Física brasileira. Referências: LINHALES, Meily Assbú. A escola, o esporte e a ‘energização do caráter’: projetos culturais em circulação na Associação Brasileira de Educação (1925-1935). 2006. 266f. Tese (Doutorado em Educação). Belo Horizonte: UFMG, 2006. PARK, Roberta J. Science, Service, and the professionalization of Physical Education: 1885-1905. In: The International Journal of the History of Sport. Vol.24, nº12, December 2007, 1674-1700. SEVCENKO, Nicolau. A Capital Irradiante: técnica, ritmos e ritos do Rio. In:______. (Org). História da Vida Privada no Brasil. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras, 1998, vol. 03. 62 Instituição Anderson da Cunha Baía Universidade Federal de Viçosa [email protected] Andrea Moreno Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais [email protected] 63 Carolina Fernandes da Silva, Alice Beatriz Assmann, Ester Liberato Pereira y Janice Zarpellon Mazo Título: Associativismo esportivo: decifranco seus sentidos Resumo: As associações esportivas são composições centradas em práticas esportivas; mas, os sentidos atribuídos pelos homens a esta estrutura podem modificar-se ao longo do tempo, juntamente com as transformações culturais. Tal interpretação é baseada em teorias do campo da História Cultural (CHARTIER, 2000; BURKE, 2005; PESAVENTO, 2004), que procuram decifrar os sentidos conferidos ao mundo por meio das representações que indivíduos e grupos constroem sobre a realidade. O termo ‘associativismo esportivo’ é formado por duas palavras que, juntas, agregam sentido uma à outra. Como conceito geral, identificamos as associações esportivas como grupamentos voluntários, de duas ou mais pessoas, que se identificam e que buscam a realização de um objetivo em comum ao praticar uma atividade esportivizada, onde são construídas representações que dão sentido ao mundo (BOUBON, 1990; LÜSCHEN; SAGE, 1981). A organização de associações foi uma estratégia adotada pelos imigrantes no sentido de promover a integração e construir meios de identificação (BURKE, 2009; MAZO, 2003), ou seja, espaços onde se exerciam as identidades culturais. A identidade cultural é, enquanto representação, uma construção imaginária de sentido, que produz coesão social e organiza um sistema compreensivo a partir da ideia de pertencimento e de diferença, através de oposições simbólicas (PESAVENTO, 2008; CUCHE, 1999). Muitas vezes, os próprios termos utilizados para se denominar as associações esportivas fornecem representações que aprovisionam sentido à instituição. Os sentidos das associações esportivas modificaram-se no processo de modernização das sociedades e passaram de identificadores étnicos para distinguidores sociais. O esporte moderno institucionalizado nas associações, a partir de 1870, constituiu-se em uma “tradição inventada” (HOBSBAWN, 1984, p. 9) pelo Estado e pelos grupos sociais específicos como resposta às modificações sociais. Referências: BOUDON, R. Dicionário de Sociologia. Lisboa: Publicações Dom Quixote, 1990. BURKE, P. O que é história cultural? Rio de Janeiro: Jorge Zahar, 2005. BURKE, P. O historiador como colunista. Editora: Civilização Brasileira, São Paulo, 2009. CHARTIER, R. A História Cultural: entre práticas e representações. Editora DIFEL 82: Portugal, 2002. CUCHE, Denys. A noção de cultura nas ciências sociais. Bauru, SP: EDUSC, 1999. HOBSBAWN, E.; RANGER, T. (orgs.). A invenção das tradições. 2ª ed. Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1984. LÜSCHEN, G.; SAGE, G. (eds). Handbook of Social Science of Sport. Champign, Illinois: Stipes Publishng Company, 1981. MAZO, Janice. Emergência e a Expansão do Associativismo Desportivo em Porto Alegre (1867-1945): espaço de representação da identidade cultural teuto-brasileira. Tese Doutorado. Faculdade de Educação Física e Ciências do Desporto, Universidade do Porto, Portugal, 2003. PESAVENTO, S. História & História Cultural. 2. ed. 2. reimp. – Belo Horizonte: Autênctica, 2008. Instituição Carolina Fernandes da Silva Alice Beatriz Assmann [email protected] Ester Liberato Pereira Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul Janice Zarpellon Mazo Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul 64 Adroaldo Gaya Título: O jogo de bola entre os espelhos Resumo: O ensaio trata da natureza do conhecimento nas Ciências do Esporte. Uma abordagem epistemológica. O autor relata uma viagem ao interior do país. Descreve, através dos espelhos retrovisores de seu carro, o jogo de bola de crianças numa várzea à beira da estrada. Propõe uma metáfora. Serve de inspiração as imagens em distintas perspectivas observadas pelo espelho côncavo (esquerdo) e convexo (direito) do carro. São duas imagens. Definem os físicos: imagem real em espelhos côncavos, imagens virtuais nos convexos. Que imagem pretendem fisiologistas, biomecânicos, psicólogos, sociólogos e pedagogos do esporte em seus espelhos refletir? Creio que independente do espelho que detêm, cada um tem a pretensão de refletir a imagem real. São cegos às imagens refletidas nos espelhos alheios. É assim. Se os nossos conhecimentos são interpretações do mundo que traduzimos em discursos, como determinar quais discursos revelam imagens reais ou virtuais? Quais os critérios que podem atribuir aos pesquisadores das várias áreas das Ciências do Esporte a convicção de que seus discursos, cada um a seu modo, são reveladores da imagem real? Quem, entre todos, possui o espelho mágico? Ou serão múltiplos os espelhos: da fisiologia, da biomecânica, da psicologia, da pedagogia. Mas, também acredito que nenhum desses múltiplos discursos seja capaz de revelar a complexidade do jogo de bola das crianças à beira da estrada. Não obstante, existe a necessidade de exercitar a arte da mediação. Quanto maior é o uso de um único espelho, maior é a possibilidade de que ele adquiria vida própria. E quando isso acontece, em vez do esporte se ver refletido no espelho, é o espelho a pretender que o esporte se reflita nele. É hora do jogo de bola ser jogado entre os espelhos. Instituição Adroaldo Gaya Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] 65 Adroaldo Gaya, Vinícius Cardoso, Anelise Gaya y Carlê Ribas Título: Talento esportivo: teoria e prática Resumo: Como ponto de partida reconhecemos que, embora muitas pessoas estejam capacitadas a praticar alguma modalidade esportiva no seu tempo de lazer, poucas estão capacitadas para o alto rendimento esportivo. Assim, quando se planejam políticas para o esporte de alto rendimento, incluise estratégias para a seleção dos futuros atletas de elite. Investir em pesquisas e programas capazes de identificar e promover talentos esportivos com elevada eficiência é o que fazem os mais destacados países da elite esportiva mundial. Entretanto, os modelos de identificação de talentos esportivos são pouco eficientes. Devido a complexidade das relações entre os diversos indicadores de desempenho esportivo, os modelos de intervenção não dão conta de prever com a desejada antecedência e a necessária eficiência, quem serão, a médio e a longo prazo, os atletas de sucesso. Como tal, se consideramos a reconhecida ineficiência dos modelos de identificação de talentos esportivos (as práticas), ainda assim, devemos insistir em operar com definições (teorias), que embora possam ser formalmente coerentes e consensuais, não apresentam validade empírica? Neste ensaio, procuramos demonstrar que as definições de talento esportivo são abstrações teóricas, sem sentido prático e validade operacional e, por suposto, sem validade científica. Como tal, devem ser abandonadas.. Instituição Adroaldo Gaya Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] Vinícius Cardoso Anelise Gaya Carlê Ribas 66 Clézio Gonçalves Título: Concepções sobre mente e corpo entre professores que atuam com modalidades esportivas Palavras-chave: concepções, corpo/mente; filosofia da mente Resumo: É recorrente na educação física o discurso de se trabalhar com a aprendizagem do movimento ou do gesto esportivo na perspectiva de integração da mente e corpo do aluno. Mas quando se questiona, a respeito de que concepção epistemológica o docente está abordando, alguns problemas começam a aparecer. O presente trabalho buscou identificar as concepções da relação Mente/Cérebro e Corpo de professores que atuam com modalidades esportivas, em escolas da rede pública e/ou privada. O trabalho caracteriza-se como uma investigação descritiva com análise qualitativa. Para tanto foi utilizado um questionário composto por cinco questões fechadas e uma aberta, validado por pesquisadores da área. Os professores atuam desde a Educação Infantil, Ensino Fundamental e do Ensino Médio. O objetivo deste estudo foi analisar as respostas dos professores e identificar nas atuais teorias que discutem a relação Corpo/Mente em quais referências os sujeitos pesquisados se encontram. Os resultados mostraram que os professores sabem dizer que existe uma relação mente/cérebro, mas não conseguem identificar a abordagem epistemológica conceitual daí derivada. Mais da metade dos professores desta pesquisa afirmam que corpo e mente são a mesma substância situando-se, portanto, numa perspectiva Monista. Os demais dizem ser substâncias diferentes defendendo uma perspectiva Dualista. Paradoxalmente aqueles que afirmam trabalhar o aluno nos processos de aprendizagem numa perspectiva integral, e de forma global, representam quase a totalidade dos entrevistados. Torna-se contraditória esta afirmativa deles. Por fim, verificou-se que os professores falam sobre a relação Corpo/Mente sem terem uma referência teórica como base ou como ponto de partida para iniciar uma discussão consistente sobre o assunto. Além disto, os atuais avanços das neurociências e as reflexões da Filosofia da Mente não são vistos como elementos necessários de aprofundamento nas relações de aprendizado em sala de aula. Instituição Clézio Gonçalves [email protected] 67 Clézio Gonçalves Título: Corpo, Olimpíadas e esporte: Entre cyborgs, organismos e virtualidades... qual a próxima fronteira? Palavras-chave: corpo, corporeidade, Olímpiada, cyborgs Resumo: Este resumo é uma reflexão sobre que tipo de corpo participará das Olimpíadas nos anos futuros. Muito já se escreveu sobre o nascimento das atuais Olimpíadas e sua evolução a medida que novas modalidades foram incluídas em suas modalidades. O evento revelou-se um espaço único de inclusão social ao implantarem os Jogos Paralímpicos, oportunizado a milhares de pessoas uma oportunidade de encontro entre sujeitos com diferentes funcionalidades e nações num momento singular de integração. Mas os atuais avanços da ciência em diferentes campos (Neurociência, Inteligência Artificial, Computação quântica, Nanotecnologia, Biologia Sintética, etc) vem realizando pesquisas que intervém na anatomia e nas condições funcionais desta estrutura corpo que já têm seu design inalterado há milhares de anos. Hoje existem possibilidades regenerativas de segmentos corporais que apontam caminhos futuros para amputados. Neste caso, um atleta paralímpico que recupera seu membro competirá na modalidade ou deixará de pertencer à mesma? E no caso das pesquisas sobre a recuperação da visão na utilização com artefatos que permitem um tipo de visão que está em estágio inicial? E no caso de tetraplégicos que recuperam sua mobilidade funcional, através de exoesqueletos, constituirá uma categoria a partir dos modelos derivados de atualização de software? Hoje já existem pessoas amputadas que dispõem de próteses que potencializam sua mobilidade em melhor desempenho que aqueles que participam dos Jogos Olímpicos. As pesquisas nanotecnológicas inaugurou discussão sobre as possíveis alterações genéticas já no estágio fetal. Neste sentido, como serão estes futuros atletas? Geneticamente programados para quebrar recordes? Serão estes conceitos questionáveis para as Olimpíadas futuras? A noção de corporeidade amplia algumas discussões, mas ainda necessita de maiores pesquisas e estudos. São questões que parecem derivadas da ficção científica, mas considerando-se os atuais avanços da ciência em diferentes áreas, não se podem desconsiderar as possibilidades de reflexão conceitual e ética que as mesmas remetem, pois a partir destas definições, se estará consolidando ou não o famoso ideal olímpico. Instituição Clézio Gonçalves [email protected] 68 Jesús Ilundáin-Agurruza Título: El cultivo estético y deportivo de la vida: unos apuntes fenomenológicos Palavras-chave: fenomenología, estética, deporte, Ortega, Sheets-Johnstone Resumo: La presentación describe los caminos por los que un etos deportivo, estético, y existencial, en próxima consonancia con el cultivo de habilidades, lleva a una vida enriquecida. La descripción de tales caminos conlleva una consideración de la vida misma como fenómeno y una estimación del los deportes en termino de las experiencias cualitativas que éstos nos permiten. El aspecto cualitativo toma carácter estético y existencial por ende. Estos elementos son engarzados por medio de los análisis fenomenológicos de Maxine Sheets-Johnstone en lo que se refiere a la dinámica cualitativa, y las “meditaciones” de José Ortega y Gasset en lo que concierne al aspecto estético-existencial. El argumento, en breve, es que los deportes enriquecen nuestras vidas al fomentar la excelencia personal, potenciar nuestras habilidades, y domar la exuberancia propia del etos deportivo orteguiano. Referências: Ortega y Gasset, J. Ortega y Gasset, J. 2001-2010. Obras Completas. Vols. I-X. Madrid: Taurus Sheets-Johnstone, M. 2009. The corporeal turn. Exeter: Imprint Academic Sheets-Johnstone, M. 2011. The Primacy of Movement, 2nd ed., Amsterdam & Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Co. Instituição Jesús Ilundáin-Agurruza Linfield College [email protected] 69 Ester Liberato Pereira, Eduardo Klein Carmona y Janice Zarpellon Mazo Título: A caça à raposa em Porto Alegre-Brasil: uma abordagem referenciada em Elias e Dunning Palavras-chave: caça à raposa, história do Esporte, mimeses, catarse Resumo: Os autores Elias e Dunning (1992) apresentam dois conceitos, denominados mimeses e catarse, como possíveis efeitos produzidos pelo esporte. Mimeses está associado ao fato de que o esporte imita, de forma seletiva, uma luta da vida real. Enquanto que catarse são emoções alegres que, por meio da prática esportiva, são vivenciadas, assim como em outros aspectos da vida. Os referidos autores (1992) abordam a caça à raposa como a expressão de um avanço de civilização, por meio de um processo de esportivização, com a criação de regras que diminuíam a violência na realização desta, evidenciando uma racionalização da prática. Este estudo busca compreender como os conceitos de mimeses e catarse são evidenciados na prática da caça à raposa em Porto Alegre na primeira metade do século XX. Na conjuntura porto-alegrense, percebe-se o descarte do excitamento de um jogo violento, representado pelos cães e a raposa, em suas configurações originais. Em Porto Alegre, a raposa era representada por um cavaleiro/amazona, montado (a) em um cavalo, que fugia dos caçadores a cavalo, os quais tinham que alcançar a raposa e tocá-la. Foram elaboradas regras peculiares, que valorizavam o trajeto da caça. Deste modo, a caça a raposa sugere a mimese da valorização de uma luta por uma conquista pessoal/profissional da vida, já que o momento da perseguição é mais apreciado em detrimento do desfecho com a captura da raposa. A excitação da perseguição à raposa também explica a forma como o conceito de catarse foi apropriado na caça à raposa porto-alegrense, já que as emoções sentidas ao transpor obstáculos e perseguir um cavaleiro/amazona sem conhecer previamente o percurso, remontam, por exemplo, a sentimentos de coragem, para os quais é dada vazão em outros aspectos da vida, apresentando, assim, um caráter de exaltação, semelhante às representações de distinção social conferidas por esta prática Instituição Ester Liberato Pereira Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul Eduardo Klein Carmona Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] Janice Zarpellon Mazo Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul 70 Marcela Mangeón, María Marta Quintana y Laura Quintana Título: El lugar del otro en las prácticas deportivas. Una interpretación filosófica-política Resumo: Este trabajo tiene como propósito central reflexionar sobre las clases de Educación Física y los supuestos que subyacen en las mismas, atendiendo a las dimensiones éticas y políticas implicadas. Más precisamente, se busca interrogar qué sentidos inciden -en el presente- en las prácticas escolarizadas, donde el deporte es un medio para educar. Los supuestos que subyacen a las prácticas deportivas y el posicionamiento del docente con respecto a su enseñanza, juegan un papel fundamental en la transmisión con respecto a los procesos de de-subjetivación (Foucault) y de subjetivación, lo cual puede ser problematizado por medio de la noción de “hospitalidad" –entendida como- un modo de relación primordialmente ética, es decir, de apertura al otro. (Derrida; Lévinas). En esta dirección, entonces, entendemos que la relación entre deporte y filosofía resulta altamente fructífera para criticar y desnaturalizar la hegemonía de un modelo de deporte selectivocompetitivo, respecto del cual la ‘eficiencia’ y la ‘productividad’ –inscriptas en la trama del consumo y el capitalismo- operan como valores sustanciales. Por ejemplo, es posible preguntar si acaso cuando en Educación Física se “seleccionan” estudiantes para conformar grupos de trabajo o para representar a la escuela, se está adhiriendo de alguna manera a esta ideología individualista, competitiva, al triunfo de unos sobre otros, al derecho de algunos, no de todos. De este modo, la historia motriz y el rendimiento para el ojo de otro, dejan al estudiante adentro o afuera de las diferentes experiencias educativas. Entonces, ¿de qué modos, quiénes y bajo qué entramados subjetivos y político institucionales, se definen las identidades de los jóvenes? ¿Cuál es el lugar particular que ocupan las instituciones educativas, en la producción de subjetividad adolescente y juvenil? Muchas veces ocurre en las clases de Educación Física que se reduce al otro- estudiante a la mismidad, a lo que uno es, tal como si fuera un espejo y donde no cabe lugar a la alteridad que intenta resistirse a la desubjetivación, es decir a no ser reconocido como sujeto que piensa, sueña, ama, imagina y produce creativamente. Estas relaciones intersubjetivas y donde no hay un sujeto que aloje, desestiman el deseo de estar y pertenecer, a partir de la imposibilidad. Hoy estamos en presencia de oportunidades de política-curricular que llevan a redefinir esta relación Filosofía y Deporte. Esta interpretación, dispuesta en términos de corte filosófico- político, requiere en primera instancia plantear el telón de fondo –epistemología- de una Educación Pública que contemple el deporte para todos y todas, y no el deporte selectivo en tiempos de diversidad e inclusión. Desde una ética de la transmisión y en tiempos de inclusión social y educativa, es necesario repensar las prácticas deportivas y recomponer el campo del semejante, donde se pone en juego el pensar la responsabilidad que tenemos como docentes y el modo en que ofrecemos un lugar y hacemos mundo. El otro, al mismo tiempo en que nos trasciende, nos constituye. En este sentido, es necesario comprender que en el deporte la diversidad se reúne en lo común pero, para esto, es necesario valorar y habilitar al otro donde se pone en juego la intersubjetividad. Al pensar las conexiones posibles entre Filosofía y Deporte, nos preguntamos ¿qué es lo que hace del deporte un tema privilegiado de prácticas, discursos e imaginarios en las sociedades modernas? Es por esto necesario, en primer término, considerarlo como un campo de análisis, estudio e investigación que posibilite repensarlo y replantearlo como práctica social y cultural, compleja y multidimensional. 71 Filosofía y Deporte requieren poder comprender las relaciones entre práctica, ideología y poder, desnaturalizando justificaciones sedimentadas.ciais. Instituição Marcela Mangeón Universidad Nacional de Entre Ríos Universidad Autonoma de Entre Ríos Universidad del Salvador [email protected] María Marta Quintana Universidad Nacional de Rio Negro Universidad Nacional del Comahue [email protected] Laura Quintana Instituto Superior de Educación Fisica, Concordia [email protected] 72 Sara Martínez Mares Título: La experiencia del logro en el deporte y algunos argumentos contra el dopaje genético Palavras-chave: Frankl, logro, superación, dopaje genético, libertad Resumo: Trataré de exponer, primeramente, la experiencia de logro humano que subyace al fenómeno deportivo rescatando una conferencia pronunciada por el psiquiatra Viktor Frankl, en el año 1972 5. En segundo lugar, las ideas expuestas aquí me servirán para criticar el modelo de deporte que favorece la postura de introducir el dopaje genético. Comienza Frankl la ponencia de la siguiente manera: “Se obstruye el paso a la inteligencia del deporte como fenómeno humano (…), mientras nuestro análisis se guíe por un modelo antropológico anticuado según el cual el hombre es un ser que experimenta ciertas necesidades y tiende a satisfacerlas a fin de evitar tensiones.6” Partiendo de la crítica al modelo freudiano, expondrá una concepción del deporte antropológicamente contraria: 7 “El ser humano no sólo no tiende a evitar tensiones a toda costa sino que las necesita.” 8 A esto se le añade que cuando no las encuentra, las crea. Pero ¿por qué no habría de encontrar tensiones? Su propuesta viene de la mano de una crítica social que sigue vigente: nuestra sociedad, desarrollada desde la época industrial, junto con el estado del bienestar, deja muchas necesidades satisfechas, y la sociedad del consumo crea nuevas. De tal forma que, ciertamente tenemos ventajas económicas, pero disponemos de demasiado tiempo libre. Nuestro drama es que muchas veces no sabemos qué hacer con este tiempo, y por eso el fenómeno deportivo se introduce en este contexto, siendo más una ascética secular9 que una catarsis moderna. Dicho en otras palabras más cómicas: “necesitando”, al parecer, de las comodidades de la tecnología 10, se podría decir de nosotros que ya no caminamos tanto --porque usamos el automóvil –y no subimos –porque utilizamos el ascensor –, pero que, sin embargo, nos da por escalar montañas. Así pues, la propuesta del autor es que el deporte competitivo bien entendido es similar al sexto grado del alpinismo: “superar la frontera de lo humanamente posible.” Sólo si el deportista lucha por superarse a sí mismo obtendrá dos efectos prácticos de interés general: no se “agarrotará” frente Simposio científico internacional convocado por el comité organizador de los juegos olímpicos de München, en 1972. El título de la conferencia es “El deporte como fenómeno humano: ¿Catarsis moderna o ascética secular?”, en Frankl (1990) El hombre doliente, Herder, Barcelona. 6 Todas las citas extraídas forman parte de la ponencia citada. (Óp. Cit. Pág. 51) 7 Exposición que, además de ofrecer un discurso altamente motivador de cara a la práctica deportiva, suministra importantes aplicaciones que dificultan una crítica general hacia la tesis del autor. Las aplicaciones se mencionan posteriormente, pero para tenerlas presentes son las siguientes: Frankl ofrece claves para superar la típica paralización o agarrotamiento del deportista antes de una competición, con lo que él denomina “derreflexión paradójica”; se trata de terapia ligada al sentido del humor con uno mismo. Esta paralización proviene, normalmente, del ansia de la victoria, por lo que acentúa la importancia de tener una actitud no centrada sólo en el hecho de ganar a toda costa, ya que la experiencia nos permite ver que el que tiene esta última actitud normalmente obtiene el efecto contrario. 8 Óp. Cit. Pág. 52. 9 El concepto de “ascética secular” se refiere al hecho de la autosuperación. En nuestra sociedad de la abundancia, “el ser humano se crea de modo artificial y deliberado ciertas situaciones de penuria” y fuerza su rendimiento porque necesita crearse tensiones. El deporte es una forma de crear tensiones, por eso, “incluso cuando el ser humano es más bien espectador y hace deporte pasivamente, busca la tensión.” (Frankl 1972, pág. 53) 10 Comodidades crecientes basadas mayormente en el ideario del modelo económico liberal: más eficiencia y producción en el menor tiempo posible. 5 73 al adversario11 y el nivel de satisfacción será mayor12 que aquél que sólo tiene un objetivo: ganar a los demás y superar las marcas.13 Partiendo, pues, de esta tesis, nos lanzamos a nuestro segundo objetivo: criticar algunos supuestos de posturas favorables al dopaje genético de acuerdo a tres líneas argumentativas: 1. Según Miah, el espíritu deportivo ya no le interesa más a nadie. Pero esto es falso: el logro humano es una experiencia importante, no sólo en el deporte, sino en el juego, en la percepción de la belleza, la música, en un trabajo, etc. 2. Contra presupuestos de Savulescu, no es del todo cierto que estimular la libertad eligiendo cómo queremos ser, a través de una manipulación externa, favorece el estabilizar nuestra identidad y contribuye al bienestar. La emoción de la admiración, presente en el fenómeno deportivo, está ligada a la experiencia de liberación que surge principalmente con el hecho no controlar las circunstancias exteriores o manipularlas a nuestro gusto. Referências: Frankl, V.: “El deporte como fenómeno humano. ¿Catarsis moderna o ascética secular?”, en Frankl (1990) El hombre doliente, Herder: Barcelona. Frankfurt, H.: (1982) “The Importance of What We Care About”, Synthese, vol 53, no.2; reeditado en (y tomado de) The Importance of What We Care About (2007a), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Savulescu, J.: (2012) ¿Decisiones peligrosas?: Una bioética desafiante. Tecnos, Madrid (Introducción y traducción de E. Bonete y B. Rodríguez). Instituição Sara Martínez Mares Universidad Católica de Valencia [email protected] Caso a comentar: el portero de Barcelona Robert Enke. Caso a comentar: el alpinista Iñaki Ochoa. 13 La causa principal es que cuanto más se ansía la victoria, más se escapa ésta de las manos.” (Ibíd. Pág. 54). De esta frase se desprenden, a mi entender, dos vertientes dignas de comentario. La primera, a modo de ejemplo, como dicen ciertos testimonios recogidos por Frankl, “en el momento en que el deportista prevé el éxito, disminuye el rendimiento.” (Ibíd. Pág.: 56). Que, por ejemplo, ciertos equipos potentes de fútbol den por supuesta la victoria ante equipos “de segunda” hace que, a veces, sorprendentemente pierdan o que el partido sea sumamente aburrido. Y la segunda vertiente, es un fenómeno ligado a la ambición característica del ser humano que no se contenta con haber ganado alguna vez. Caso a comentar: el ciclista Lance Armstrong. 11 12 74 Marcelo Moraes y Fernando Marinho Mezzadri Título: Esporte e a Estética: um diálogo com Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht e Michel Foucault Palavras-chave: esporte, corpo, estética Resumo: O campo intelectual, ao aplicar ferramentas das ciências humanas acaba por atribuir ao esporte uma carga altamente negativa. Mesmo sociólogos simpáticos ao esporte, como o alemão Norbert Elias e o francês Pierre Bourdieu, acabaram por emitir críticas a esta manifestação. Elias, por exemplo, explicou a ascensão do esporte como um estágio da civilização ocidental que serviu para subjugar os corpos dos indivíduos. Já na análise do sociólogo francês, foi atribuída ao esporte a causa da diferenciação e da distinção social. Hodiernamente é comum se falar que o motor de um evento esportivo é apenas e tão somente o interesse econômico. Ironicamente, o inverso dessa visão – transformar o esporte num meio de identificação com os oprimidos, como tendem a fazer alguns intelectuais e acadêmicos – não constitui grande avanço, pois se trata mais uma vez de escrever sobre o fenômeno esportivo em nome de princípios éticos e/ou morais, que estão localizados fora do esporte. Nesse sentido, o presente trabalho não pretende sucumbir ao encanto metafísico de interpretação e sim tratar o mesmo como um digno objeto estético. Para valorizar esta dimensão ampara-se nas definições de Immanuel Kant; nas contribuições do crítico literário alemão Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht; e nas análises da estética da existência do filosofo francês Michel Foucault. As apreciações kantianas sobre os conceitos de “belo” e “sublime” se tornam de fundamental importância para a aproximação do mesmo com a teoria estética. Gumbrecht, ao aproximar o esporte destes conceitos kantianos, aponta que tais definições se materializam nos “momentos singulares” que uma refinada performance esportiva proporciona. Neste momento as contribuições de Foucault, sobre a estética da existência, tornam-se muito profícuas, visto que os “momentos singulares” sugeridos por Gumbrecht podem ser vistas, dentro dos moldes foucaultianos, como verdadeiras “artes da existência”. Para compreender essa dinâmica filosófica foram selecionadas como fontes documentais as biografias de cinco atletas de renome mundial: Airton Senna, Lance Armstrong, Roger Federer, Michael Jordan e Emil Zatopek. No contato com os documentos elencados foi possível visualizar que os desempenhos esportivos destes atletas proporcionaram diversos “momentos singulares”, “artes da existência” e/ou “técnicas de si” muito peculiares. Sendo assim, a principal conclusão do presente trabalho é a de que estes esportistas de renome mundial extrapolam os ditames éticos e/ou morais, pois a sua constante busca pelo “domínio de si” exigida pelo esporte de alto rendimento acaba por produzir formas de vida muito peculiares e, consequentemente, novas práticas de liberdade são produzidas. Referências: FOUCAULT, M. A Hermenêutica do Sujeito. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2004. GUMBRECHT, H. U. Elogio da beleza atlética. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras, 2005. KANT, I. Crítica da faculdade do juízo. Rio de Janeiro: Forense Universitária, 1995. Instituição Marcelo Moraes Universidade Federal do Paraná [email protected] Fernando Marinho Mezzadri Universidade Federal do Paraná 75 Marcelo Moraes e Silva, Aline Jorge Corrêa, Fernando Marinho Mezzadri, Palmira Sevegnani y Katiuscia Mello Figuerôa Título: O Esporte brasileiro entre dilemas epistemológicos: da acusação à busca por absolvição Palavras-chave: esporte; educação física; epistemologia Resumo: O presente artigo visa remontar as fontes utilizadas no “processo jurídico”, a que o Esporte fora acometido a partir da década de 1980 no Brasil. Neste período, marcado por novas estruturações da sociedade brasileira, verificou-se que uma nascente epistemologia da área levou o Esporte ao “banco dos réus”. Juntaram “provas” e apresentaram as mesmas à “corte”. Acusando com veemência, acabaram levando o “réu” à condenação. (Medina, 1983; Oliveira, 1983; Cavalcanti, 1984; Bracht, 1986; Betti, 1991). Este conjunto de trabalhos tornou-se o primeiro grupo de fontes utilizadas na elaboração do presente ensaio. A “sentença” emitida por estes autores foi um apontamento da necessidade das práticas esportivas elaborarem novas pedagogias, principalmente se as mesmas tivessem relação com os processos de escolarização. Afinal era “necessário” preservar a infância e juventude dos malefícios que o Esporte poderia acarretar em suas formações. Baseado nesta sentença foi que surgiu o conjunto de obras que constituíram o segundo bloco de análise deste estudo (Coletivo de Autores, 1992; Kunz, 1994; Assis de Oliveira, 2001). Reflexões que buscaram elaborar estas novas pedagogias para o ensino do esporte nas escolas brasileiras. Sendo assim, o texto busca remontar as fontes utilizadas durante todo esse “processo jurídico”, para compreender quais foram as intenções presentes no julgamento epistemológico que levou o Esporte a condenação pela Educação Física brasileira. Afinal, o Esporte, o principal “réu” dos anos 1980 ,foi “julgado” justamente? O que se verificou ao remontar as fontes é que há a necessidade de continuar a discussão. O que a história expôs sobre o “réu” é que a forma com que ele foi “julgado” acarretou consequências para o âmbito da Educação Física brasileira. Nesse “julgamento”, a acusação clamava por um olhar especial no âmbito escolar, para tanto, apresentavam uma compreensão do que o Esporte poderia causar à infância e à juventude, quando adentrasse o espaço escolar. As “provas” organizadas foram suficientes para que o Esporte fosse “condenado” e a “causa ganha”. Sua “sentença” consistia em alcançar uma prática nova, baseada em uma epistemologia crítica, somente através destas ações é que o mesmo poderia alcançar a “absolvição”. Nesse sentido, é possível afirmar que o Esporte foi condenado principalmente pela busca dos promotores por uma melhor colocação no espaço acadêmico. O Esporte ficou marcado pelos “promotores”, que fizeram dele o baluarte de seus primeiros “casos” ou, como se viu neste artigo, os autores da Educação Física brasileira se utilizaram de uma acepção esportiva para incitar discussões no meio acadêmico e iniciar os primeiros estudos em torno da epistemologia, proporcionando com isso a valorização de um discurso que deram aos promotores do caso uma maior visibilidade e uma melhor posição no campo acadêmico brasileiro. Para finalizar, esse olhar elencado para o contexto de “condenação” e “absolvição” do Esporte, reporta-se sobre a necessidade de continuar a discussão, pois a única coisa que se sabe sobre o “caso”, é que ainda é discutido – não mais pelos que participaram da “corte” sublevada para “julgar” o Esporte, mas outros que ainda estão a procurar e a “remontar” as fontes para continuar “condenando” e/ou “absolvendo” o Esporte. Referências: BOURDIEU, P. Questões de Sociologia. Rio de Janeiro: Marco Zero, 1983. FOUCAULT, M. Palavras e as Coisas: Uma arqueologia das ciências humanas.. Martins Fontes. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2000. GUMBRECHT, H. U. Elogio da beleza atlética. São Paulo: Companhia das Letras, 2005. 76 Instituição Marcelo Moraes Universidade Federal do Paraná [email protected] Aline Jorge Corrêa Universidade Federal do Paraná Fernando Marinho Mezzadri Universidade Federal do Paraná Palmira Sevegnani Universidade Federal do Paraná Katiuscia Mello Figuerôa Universidade Federal do Paraná 77 Elizabeth Pedrosa Ribeiro Título: Empatia e vontade de vencer Palavras-chave: empatia, vontade de vencer, ética, esporte Resumo: O esporte com frequência nos confronta com comportamentos que rompem com as regras morais, tornando irrelevantes valores como a honestidade e o respeito aos outros. A busca da vitória parece exigir dos atletas um certo grau de "imoralidade" (simulações e faltas provocadas intencionalmente, bem como provocações e mesmo agressões não são exatamente raras em esportes coletivos; em esportes individuais, o doping é um exemplo bem conhecido). Seriam esses comportamentos inerentes à prática do esporte? Por outro lado, estudos recentes mostram que tais condutas dependem de certa anulação ou bloqueio dos mecanismos empáticos em nosso cérebro. Ao que parece, para que haja uma "vontade de vencer", é preciso menos empatia do que a moralidade exige. Contudo, sentimentos empáticos são condições necessárias para que haja comportamentos morais adequados. Por outro lado, para que a competição aconteça é necessário que se manifeste uma vontade de vencer naqueles que estão competindo. Isso representa um problema para pensar a ética no esporte, visto que a vontade de vencer pode ser uma vontade desimpedida de ganhar. Porém, um desportista não pode deixar de cumprir seus deveres éticos para com o outro, seja ele seu adversário ou companheiro de equipe. Parece óbvio, assim, que a ética também deve conduzir as ações humanas no meio desportivo. Também as relações entre as instituições que lidam com o esporte devem ser conduzidas eticamente, sendo, assim, baseadas em vínculos empáticos. Neste trabalho, assumimos que somos seres morais e empáticos por natureza, que a empatia pode ser desenvolvida ou reprimida por uma série de contingências. Por outro lado, assumimos também que a vontade de vencer é uma dessas contingências, sendo inerente à competição. Assim, quanto mais importantes forem as consequências de uma vitória, maior será a possibilidade de se violarem regras a favor de interesses próprios. A reação de uma pessoa à vitória, ao sucesso, à fama, ao reconhecimento ou à aceitação revela dessa forma seu próprio caráter. Conjugar empatia e vontade de vencer significa conjugar variáveis morais eventualmente opostas; ambas, porém, necessárias para que o próprio esporte exista. Referências: AZEVEDO, Marco Antonio. Levando o Esporte a Sério. In: ROHDEN, Luiz; AZEVEDO, Marco Antonio; AZAMBUJA, Celso Cândido de. FILOSOFIA E FUTEBOL: troca de passes. Porto Alegre: Sulina, 2012. NIETZSCHE, Friedrich Wilhelm. Vontade de Potência. Disponível em: http://pensamentosnomadas. files.wordpress.com/2012/11/a-vontade-de-poder.pdf. Acesso em: 16/07/2013. SMITH, Adam. Teoria dos Sentimentos Morais. Trad.: Lya Luft; rev.: Eunice Ostrensky. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 1999 Instituição Elizabeth Pedrosa Ribeiro Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] 78 Paulo Rodrigo Pedroso da Silva y Lamartine P. DaCosta Título: O pensamento heurístico de Occam aplicado ao problema filosófico do doping no esporte Palavras-chave: doping, Aristóteles, Descartes, Occam Resumo: O problema filosófico de banimento de drogas e procedimentos para a obtenção artificial de resultados nas competições esportivas foi resumido recentemente por Schneider (2014) por quatro argumentos correntes que tem se mantidos inconclusivos desde a criação da World Anti-doping Agency (WADA) em 1999: trapaça, vantagem injusta, prejudicial aos usuários e perversão da natureza do esporte (desumanização). Para esta autora seminal da temática do doping, cada uma dessas abordagens tem apresentado contradições em termos da filosofia analítica. Por outro lado a complexidade do tema em questão pode ser avaliada por suas abordagens ético-jurídicas as quais segundo Olinder (2005) comportam nove “discursos” distintos, como nos exemplos de “medicalização”, “criminalização”, “punição” etc. Não é surpreendente portanto que a problemática do doping no esporte tenha se mantido insolúvel mesmo diante do aperfeiçoamento das rotinas de controle desenvolvidos pela WADA nos seus 15 anos de existência. Neste sentido, a presente contribuição objetiva redefinir o problema do doping ampliando suas abordagens filosóficas além da citada argumentação analítica. Esta redefinição alcança a filosofia grega antiga que foi perceptível à convivência de argumentos opostos ao usar a categoria de “aporia” incluindo contradições das práticas atléticas (DaCosta, 1971). Para Aristóteles o trato com aporias implicava em “dissolver” o problema por sucessivas sínteses e análises. Já no século 17, René Descartes abordava a convivência dos contrários por sua filosofia “dualista” que se propunha a conhecer melhor as oposições para reorienta-las vis-à-vis amor vs ódio, vida vs morte, vitória vs derrota etc. Entretanto, tais soluções tem sido ao longo da historia da filosofia por vezes entendidas como reducionistas embora tenham sobrevivido pelo viés metodológico. Nesse contexto, a presente proposta focaliza o método de Occam – filósofo do século 14 – que consiste na eliminação heurística de contraditórios identificando versões mais simples capazes de reduzir a complexidade da busca de conclusões imediatas. Como tal, esta simplificação metodológica apresenta-se menos reducionista do que as categorias de análise “aporia” e “dualismo”, pois é todavia imprecisa porém mais explicativa. Por esta razão filósofos modernos como nos exemplos de Popper e Wittgenstein admitiram a validade da chamada “navalha de Occam” em suas criticas radicais ao fazer científico e filosófico. Em relação ao trato das questões de doping impõe-se portanto um repensar ao estilo de Occam de modo a reduzir ou eliminar a estratificação dos argumentos e discursos típicos de suas inquirições. Em suma, propomos a eleição de apenas um dos quatro argumentos de Schneider buscando uma única conclusão com vistas à sua operacionalização pragmática. Nesta linha de conta, nossa escolha incide sobre o argumento da perversão do esporte cuja conclusão pertinente evitará a dissolução das práticas esportivas, algo que não ocorre com os demais argumentos. Referências: Schneider, A. (2014) Doping. In Torres, C. (Ed) The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Sport. London: Bloomsbury, pp. 350-352. Olinder, K. (2005) Doping and Anti-doping Issues: An Inventory of the Social-legal State of knowledge. Stckholm: RiksidrottsForbundet, pp. 13 – 18. 79 DaSilva, P.R.P., Figueiredo, V.C., Oliveira, E., DaCosta, L.P. & Czpielewski, M.A. (2010) Odds ratio for use of anabolic steroids and other substances in fitness training gyms. Brazilian Journal of Sports and Exercise Research, Vol. 1, No. 2, 2010, pp. 122 – 126. Instituição Paulo Rodrigo Pedroso da Silva Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] Lamartine P. DaCosta Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul [email protected] 80 José Luis Pérez Triviño Título: Goles con la mano y decisiones irregulares. Una comparación entre la teoría del Derecho y la filosofía del deporte Palavras-chave: teoría del Derecho, normas irregulares, concepciones del deporte, formalismo, convencionalismo, interpretativismo Resumo: Los juegos o los deportes como actividades regladas han sido profusamente utilizados como metáfora explicativa del Derecho. Hart (1961), por ejemplo, se sirve de las reglas del cricket y del fútbol para ejemplificar la dimensión social de la regla de reconocimiento. MacIntyre y Rawls recurren también a los juegos para ejemplificar el concepto de práctica social. Un tema donde la teoría del Derecho y del deporte coinciden es el análisis de las decisiones irregulares, sentencias o normas en el ámbito jurídico, el de los goles irregulares, en el ámbito del fútbol. En ambos caso se pone de manifiesto la tensión entre las reglas y su aplicación a casos particulares. El propósito del trabajo será trasplantar el análisis de la teoría del Derecho sobre las normas irregulares al mundo del fútbol, para lo cual trataré de mostrar la similitud entre las diferentes teorías que en ambos ámbitos han analizado el mismo problema (formalismo, convencionalismo, interpretativismo). En las conclusiones trataré finalmente de exponer cuál es, en mi opinión, la forma más adecuada de enfrentarse al problema de las decisiones que son a un tiempo irregulares y últimas en cualquier sistema normativo, sea jurídico o deportivo. Referências: D’AGOSTINO, F. “The Ethos of Games”, Philosophic Inquiry in Sport, W.J. Morgan and K.v. Meier (Eds.). 2nd ed. Champaign, IL: Human Kinetics, 1995. También en Journal of Sport Philosophy, VIII, 1981. LOLAND, S., Fair Play in Sport: A Moral Norm System. London & New York: Routledge, 2002. TAMBURRINI, C.M. ¿La mano de Dios? Una visión distinta del deporte, Buenos Aires, Eds. Continente, 2000. TORRES, C.-CAMPOS, D. “Los goles con la mano: ¿deben o no ser considerados como parte del juego? En ¿La pelota no dobla? Ensayos filosóficos en torno al fútbol, Buenos Aires, Ed. Zorzal, 2006. TORRES, C., “What Counts as Part of a Game? A Look at Skills”. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, XXVII, 2000. Instituição José Luis Pérez Triviño Universitat Pompeu Fabra [email protected] 81 César R. Torres Título: El boxeo y los Juegos Olímpicos de la Juventud Palavras-chave: Juegos Olímpicos de la Juventud, boxeo, salud, autonomía, Olimpismo Resumo: Los Juegos Olímpicos de la Juventud (JOJ), inaugurados en el 2010, constituyen no sólo el último emprendimiento del Comité Olímpico Internacional (COI) sino también el evento multideportivo internacional más grande para deportistas jóvenes. Su Programa Competitivo está basado en el de los Juegos Olímpicos aunque con menos disciplinas y eventos, pero con algunas disciplinas nuevas como el torneo de básquetbol de tres contra tres en medio campo de juego, y otras innovaciones como la inclusión de competencias de equipos de géneros mixtos. Si bien los JOJ están destinados a deportistas entre 15 y 18 años, cada Federación Deportiva Internacional determina el rango específico de edad para su deporte. En el caso del boxeo, los segundos JOJ que se organizarán en Nanjing, China en agosto de este año, incluirán 78 boxeadores y boxeadoras (60 hombres y 18 mujeres) entre 17 y 18 años que competirán en diez y tres categorías para hombres y mujeres respectivamente. La motivación detrás de los JOJ es tanto la competencia deportiva como los valores que han inspirado y encuadrado a los Juegos Olímpicos desde su creación a fines del siglo diecinueve. Estos valores son parte de la visión filosófica conocida como “Olimpismo”. De esta manera, como expresara Jacques Rogge, ex presidente del COI, antes del lanzamiento de los JOJ: “El principal objetivo […] no es la competencia por sí misma. El principal objetivo es dar a los jóvenes una educación basada en los valores Olímpicos”.i Dicho de otra manera, los JOJ han sido concebidos como un ingente esfuerzo pedagógico Olímpico. En el corazón de los JOJ reside el intento de familiarizar a los deportistas jóvenes con el Olimpismo y sus valores “en un espíritu divertido y festivo que despierte conciencia sobre temas importantes como los beneficios de un estilo de vida saludable, la lucha contra el dopaje, los desafíos globales y su papel como embajadores deportivos en sus comunidades”.ii En este sentido, el COI anunció en un comunicado de prensa después de que su Comité Ejecutivo aprobara los JOJ en el 2007 que “Los eventos deportivos serán elegidos cuidadosamente para proteger la salud de los jóvenes deportistas”.iii En esta ponencia argumentaré que el boxeo no es apropiado para promover los objetivos proclamados para los JOJ, y que el mismo debería ser removido del Programa Competitivo de dicho evento. Una línea argumentativa se centrará en el impacto cuestionable que el boxeo tiene en la salud de los deportistas jóvenes. Temas de autonomía, consentimiento y paternalismo serán discutidos en relación a la salud de dichos deportistas. En este sentido argumentaré no sólo que el boxeo es dañino para la salud de los deportistas jóvenes sino que también éstos podrían no poseer el nivel de autonomía requerido para permitirles que practiquen un deporte con tal riesgo de consecuencias serias e incluso irreparables para la salud. Una segunda línea argumentativa se focalizará en el propósito central del boxeo y su relación con el Olimpismo y la propagación de sus valores. Esto me permitirá argumentar que el boxeo es un deporte proclive a la violencia y por lo tanto incoherente con los valores Olímpicos. Al fin y al cabo, la aspiración educativa de los JOJ puede lograrse más efectivamente a través de otros deportes cuya práctica está mejor alineada con los ideales Olímpicos. Instituição César R. Torres The College at Brockport, State University of New York [email protected] 82 Stephen Wade, “No kidding: Teens to get Youth Olympic Games,” USA Today, April 25, 2010, http://www.usatoday.com/spo rts/olympics/2007-04-25-2774646336_x.htm (accessed November 1, 2010). i International Olympic Committee, Youth and Olympism. Olympic Studies Centre Content Package (Lausanne: International Olympic Committee, 2010), 5. ii See International Olympic Committee, “IOC Executive Board Welcomes Idea of Youth Olympic Games,” April 26, 2007, http://www.olympic.org/content/news/media-resources/manual-news/19 99-2009/2007/04/26/ioc-executive-board-wel comes-idea-of-youth-olympic-games/ (accessed November 1, 2010). iii 83