1 PUTTING HABITUS IN ITS PLACE: REJOINDER TO THE SYMPOSIUM * Loïc Wacquant University of California, Berkeley Centre européen de sociologie et de science politique, Paris ABSTRACT In this response to my critics, I amplify the conceptual clarification and methodological stipulation of habitus begun in “Homines in Extremis” to help us move from a sociology of the body as socially construc-ted object to a sociology from the body as socially construc-ting vector of knowledge, power, and practice. The specification of habitus by membership in collectives, attachment to institutions, and analytic purpose makes it a flexible multiscalar notion with which to construct the epistemic individual and account for both reproduction and change, conformity and creativity, as well as self-revision. For this, we must reject theological interpretations that rigidly lock habitus into Bourdieu‟s framework; avoid conflating the formal properties of the notion with its concrete features in specific settings and cases; and distinguish between the rhetorical invocation of his concepts (“speaking Bourdieuese”) and their effective deployment in the construction of the empirical object. As embodied and embedded capacity, habitus brings temporality, depth, and desire to the analytic epicenter. It reminds us that the social world is not transparent, open-ended, and instantaneous, but endowed with gravity, opacity, and asymmetry. Treating the sentient and skilled organism as fount of both social intelligence and sociological acumen can help historical social science connect with enactive psychology and recover the carnality of action that conventional accounts of social life routinely erase. KEYWORDS: habitus, Bourdieu, body, time, desire, social gravity, epistemic individual, construction of the object, enactive ethnography, carnal sociology I thank the contributors to this symposium for their stimulative comments, which give me an opportunity to clarify, specify, and amplify the arguments put forth in “Homines in Extremis” (Wacquant 2014a). Let me restate briefly the three main purposes of that essay. I use a set of apprentice-based studies of the practical logics of combat sports and martial arts inspired by my book on prizefighting, Body and Soul, as an empirical springboard (i) to correct prevalent mistakes and misunderstandings about habitus; (ii) to characterize its three components, cognitive, conative, and emotive, and spotlight its diverse modes of acquisition and malleability; and (iii) to adumbrate the broader mission and promise of carnal sociology as a distinctive mode of inquiry that fruitfully deploys habitus as both object and means of investigation. My article is an exercise in conceptual specification, methodological solicitation and theoretical petition intended to help move us from a social science of the body as socially construc-ted object to a social science from the body as socially construc-ting vector of knowledge, power, and practice: the fount of both social intelligence and sociological acumen that investigators should practically mobilize rather than ritually deny and discursively paralyze. My four commentators do not take issue with my aims so much as with the means I recommend to realize them. I respond to their main concerns and criticisms in seriatim, and turn some of their questions back to them, with the aim of improving our collective grasp of habitus, in the twofold sense of intellectual understanding and practical handling. A common thread will run through my responses: that, more so than any other “theorist,” one must studiously avoid 2 theoreticist readings of Bourdieu’s concepts and attend instead to their pragmatic deployment in empirical research. Most of the troubles that scholars experience with habitus will instantly vanish or get gradually resolved as soon as they abandon the scholastic posture that they typically adopt toward it.1 PARAMETERS OF HABITUS SPECIFICATION While sympathetic to an approach to which he has himself contributed both theoretically and empirically (see, in particular, Crossley 1996, 2001a and 2006), Crossley (2014: *) is concerned that habitus has become “confusing and confused, given its internal complexity and range of application.” But complexity and range need not breed confusion. The fact that habitus is indeed a multi-scalar concept that one can employ at several different levels of social activity (from the individual to the civilizational), and across degrees and types of aggregation (settings, collectives, institutions) depending on one‟s research question is precisely what allows us to make clear distinctions as well as connections between these. There is an individual habitus, the idiosyncratic product of a singular social trajectory and set of life experiences (even monozygotic twins always differ in their relation to their parents and reaction to one another) that is nonetheless the combination of shared constituents. This is what makes possible a clinical sociology, that is, the sociological study of particular personalities and their troubles (Bourdieu and Maître 1994). These individual experiences are selected and stamped by membership in collectives and attachment to institutions. On the side of collectives, we find the major principles of social vision and division, in particular those that anchor strategies of group-making (Bourdieu 1987/1989, Wacquant 2013). Thus there is a gender(ed) habitus since all humans are fitted and attuned to the masculine/feminine binary, even those who challenge its implications or cross its boundary. There is likewise a class habitus since all social agents are located in a hierarchical distribution of forms of capital rooted in or derived from the economic structure; this class habitus can be further declensed by class fraction (Bourdieu 1979/1984: 283-295, 339-346). There is an ethnic (local, regional, ethnolinguistic, ethnoreligious, ethnoracial, national, civilizational, etc.) habitus since each of these prevalent “containers” of social action making claim to collective honor tends to produce joint ways of thinking, feeling and acting, and common sets of expectations. And so on with other operative markers of social classification and stratification. On the side of institutions, we have bundles of durable dispositions specific to definite organizations (fraternities, prisons, firms, political parties, etc.) and specialized microcosms or fields: academic, artistic, political, pugilistic, juridical, scientific, etc. Settings that inculcate, cultivate and reward distinct but transposable sets of categories, skills, and desires among their participants can be fruitfully analyzed as sites of production and operation of habitus (Bourdieu 1989/1998: 71-127 and 1999). The double specification of habitus, by arena of production-activation and by analytic purpose, clears up ambiguities and prevents mixups. Similarly, the use of the latin, habitus (past participle of habere, to possess and be in a certain state) need not worry Crossley (2014: *). It is 1 Bourdieu‟s constant and urgent warnings about the dangerous delusions of the logocentric conception of action associated with the spectatorial stance of the scholar apply directly to the social (mis)uses of his work in the academy. “The Three Forms of the Scholastic Fallacy” (Bourdieu 1997/2000: chapter 4) is mandatory reading on this point for anyone aiming to appropriate his work for purposes other than professorial erudition and pedagogical routinization (as displayed, for example, by the recitation of fictitious dialogues between Bourdieu and other theorists). (I thank Tom Medvetz for his sharp comments on this article which made me see this point clearly enough to express it). 3 a help and not a hindrance, as it prods the reader to interrupt the train of conventional thinking and to reflect on the meaning and features of the notion --this is the virtue of foreign language when it is not interjected for show. It reminds us that we must beware of falling for the illusory realism of the concrete person or empirical individual, and for the naïve phraseology of the “actor” and related metaphors drawn from theater, such as “roles,” “scripts” and “kits” (Bourdieu 1984/1988, 2013: *). Habitus is a proven vaccine against these common diseases as it invites us to construct the epistemic individual, characterized by those properties (including dispositions) active in the setting under investigation and pertinent to the question pursued.2 The Latin also establishes a clean break with the notion of habit, from which habitus was separated at its birth some twenty-three centuries ago: the Greek word for habit in Aristotle, the originator of habitus as hexis, is ethos; the Latin term for habit in the work of Thomas Aquinas and the medieval Scholastics is consuetudo. Not only does habitus carry over the whole sedimented (and ongoing) social history, individual and collective, of the agent, thus enabling us to construe the body as an “ongoing practical achievement” (to use the language of Garfinkel) and an evolving matrix of capacities, which the notion of habit does not. As a dynamic system articulating multiple dispositions, it is a principle of invention via the transfer of schemata and the skewed search for rough practical coherence, which habit is not. And it can generate different, even opposite, practices, depending on the solicitations and possibilities of the social space it encounters, which habit cannot, as Crossley (2013) obliquely concedes in his comparative discussion of these two notions. It follows that it is incorrect to assert that “habitus do not revise themselves, however, and cannot be regarded as a source of creativity” (Crossley 2014: *). Quite the opposite: the habitus of the great innovators in art, music, science, or politics is precisely the precipitate of their mastery of the gamut of strategic possibilities in their field and the principle of their capacity to actualize options pregnant in it--as Bourdieu (2013) demonstrates in great detail in the case of Manet‟s “symbolic revolution” in painting, the same reasoning applying to Bourdieu in the social scientific field. Moreover, to the degree that it incorporates reflexive dispositions (nurtured by scholastic microcosms such as the religious or the academic field) and that these dispositions are applied to the agent‟s own thoughts, feelings, actions and surroundings, habitus can guide a form of self-work. Indeed, religious ascesis and psychoanalysis may be regarded as two professionally assisted work of habitus-revision, and Bourdieu himself clearly assigns such a wisdom-inducing mission to his brand of socioanalysis.3 More generally, it bears repeating that habitus can be a source of creativity whenever it is composed of disparate dispositions in tension or contradiction with one another; whenever it encounters settings that challenge its active proclivities; and when agents enter rationalized worlds that encourage the methodical reshaping of their dispositions in conformity with the dictates of “greedy institutions” (Coser 1974). Thus 2 Bourdieu (2004/2008) supplies a compact model for this analytic move in his Sketch for a Self-Analysis, which does not vivisect the private person Pierre Bourdieu in his innumerable idiosyncrasies (the foods he savors, the novelists he reads, the color of his shirts, his relations to his sons and his car mechanic, etc.) but reports on those social properties issuing from his childhood, intellectual training, and academic position that together account for the structure and proclivities of his scientific habitus --and for that part of his social being alone. 3 Assisted logotherapy or sociotherapy aimed at altering the structures and proclivities of the embodied (social) unconscious may be regarded as an upgraded version of the strategy advocated by seventeenth-century philosophers to manage the passions, chief among them Baruch Spinoza: use the one to counter the others and thereby achieve happiness. For a provocative Spinozist reading of Bourdieu‟s theory of action, see Lordon (2006). 4 the selfsame dispositional theory of action is capacious enough to account for both regularity and deviation, conformity and innovation, reproduction and change.4 Finally I must disagree with Crossley‟s reading of my work as diverging from Bourdieu to bridge with the Chicago School. Although I did my doctoral research in Chicago and I grew quite familiar with the particular tradition of field research associated with it (it is not a school in any meaningful sense of the term), I was not trained by Chicago, if only for the simple reason that no one was teaching in that vein at that time. I have registered my serious reservations regarding the built-in flaws of Chicago-style “moral empiricism” in “Scrutinizing the Street” (Wacquant 2002): among them, the naïve adoption of folk concepts, the constitutive inability to root action and cognition in social structures, the elision of embodied and objectified history, and the stubborn blindness to power. A single concern suffices to demarcate my approach from that codified by E.C. Hughes and illustrated by his erstwhile students: to lay out the structured forging and situated flowing of pugilistic desire, a notion epicentral to habitus and incompatible with the Chicago vision of the agent as disembodied animal symbolicum (notwithstanding George Herbert Mead‟s brilliant insights about the “biologic individual”). My work fits squarely in the lineage of French rationalism, running from Condorcet and Comte to Durkheim and LéviStrauss, to Mauss and Bourdieu, and it introduces the incarnate agent as suffering and desiring being at the intersection between historical structures and situated interaction.5 Now, Crossley (2014: *) is right to point to the dangers of rigidifying, reifying and anthropomorphizing the concept, but this warning applies to every social scientific construct. This is as true for habitus as for, say, petty bourgeoisie, the state, and patriarchical countertransference. Every concept is liable to be deformed, misused, and even abused, for concepts are our instruments of reasoning and observation: the work they do depends on how we work with them, that is, what we make them do in our analyses. What I do in Body & Soul (Wacquant 2004a) is to apply habitus as method to tap into the casting of the pugilistic habitus as object. Apprenticeship is the technical means, not of a solipsistic return onto the knowing subject (the person of the sociologist), but to get us closer to the phenomenon and probe its immanent makeup. The difference with auto-ethnography is very clear: the analyst is one among several sensate, suffering, and situated agents undergoing a particular “experiment,” namely, the grafting and meshing of pugilistic schemata of cognition, cathexis, and action (see Wacquant 2005: esp. 469-471 for an elaboration). Habitus-driven sociology enables us to swim in the stream of action and filter out its composition, rather than scope it from the bank. It propels us to traverse the multiple layers that mesh into the fabric of the everyday lifeworld --the forte of phenomenology as instigated by Husserl and Merleau-Ponty-- and to net the carnality of action that ordinary social science --including the Chicago school-- steadfastly erases from its accounts. 4 Numerous critics of Bourdieu, from Sewell (1992) and King (2000) to Crossley (2001b), Dalton (2004), and Hammoudi (2007), have purported to supplement Bourdieu‟s alleged “reproduction theory” with a theory of creative action. But this resolves a problem that they artificially created by truncating the capacities of habitus and portraying it as a miniature replica of a single coherent social structure condemned to perpetuate its pattern mechanically. 5 Contrary to Crossley‟s (2014: *) view, there is no opposition between “real” and “empirical” relations in Bourdieu. As I demonstrate elsewhere (Wacquant 2014b), his concepts allow us to travel with ease across scales to capture in one and the same analytic framework the most intimate of micro-experiences (say, the smell and noise of jail living), the socially determined capacities and proclivities of agents (boxers, convicts, street hustlers), meso-level containers of action (the ghetto), and the grandest of macro-structures (the penal state as component of the political project labelled neoliberalism). 5 A DETACHABLE CAPSULE FOR A DISPOSITIONAL THEORY OF ACTION Like Crossley, Paradis (2014: * ) situates herself within Bourdieu‟s approach but avers that I am not “relational” in my “treatment of habitus.” She objects that I “undersell” that approach and even “obscure” its heuristic power by not juggling with the full conceptual triplet (not “trilogy”) of “habitus, capital, and field.” In sum, I am not Bourdieusian enough for her taste. This is the first time that I encounter this argument and I find it perplexing --all the more so when Paradis repeatedly cites my work to illustrate what she deems to be the proper handling of the notion. It stems from a theological and shallow reading of Bourdieu; this reading is quite common, especially among students of the body, and we must strive to avoid it. First, like every concept partaking of a flexible and open analytic framework, and Bourdieu‟s is nothing if not that, habitus can perfectly be separated from the other notions that compose that framework, provisionally or even permanently. Indeed Bourdieu himself used every one of these notions independently on numerous occasions. First illustration: due to the minimal differentiation of economic, political, and religious authority, there were no fields in the peasant communities of late colonial Algeria that Bourdieu studied in his youthful forays into kinship, honor and power, and revisited as a testing ground for his late theory of masculine domination as paradigm of symbolic violence (Bourdieu and Sayad 1964, Bourdieu 1977/1979, 2008/2013 and 1998/2001). And yet it is on this very terrain that he first introduced and then honed the concept of habitus. Second illustration: many if not most social settings, forces, or practices in advanced society do not form fields in Bourdieu‟s sense. For instance, there is no such thing as a “sexual field” or a “racial field” for the simple reason that desire and racialization (as the naturalization of statutory gradations of honor) can and do invade and pervade multiple domains of social action. Yet one can, in some societies and for some analytic purposes, definitely speak of a sexual habitus and a racial habitus (see, Adkins and Skeggs 2004; Sallaz 2010 and Hancock 2013).6 The social scene of a stigmatized housing estate in the French urban periphery and the wasteland of the American hyperghettto are not fields; this does not obviate rolling out the notion of a “broken habitus” to account for the contradictory strategies and representations of the subproletarian young men who roam or reside in them (Bourdieu 1993/1998, Wacquant 1993/1998). Third illustration: one of the most advanced studies of a field carried out by Bourdieu retraces “A Conservative Revolution in Publishing” (Bourdieu 1999/2008) and it makes no use of habitus as it centers on the evolving morphology of positions and the nesting of that sector of cultural production into the broader field of power. Habitus is a capsule for a dispositional theory of action stressing that the agent carries her history inside of her and actively shapes her world through socially constructed instruments of construction; it may be adopted, elaborated, and criticized quite independently of Bourdieu‟s other concepts covering structure, power, and history.7 6 For a pungent critique of the sterile multiplication of “fields,” see Érik Neveu‟s (2013) “Should the Social Sciences Accumulate Capitals?” For a stimulating study of the production of the racial habitus of blacks and whites in the Southern US between 1890 and 1950, see Ritterhouse‟s (2006) Growing Up Jim Crow. Ritterhouse does not get the theoretical mileage her archival work promises due to the analytical confusion introduced by her loose usage of “etiquette,” “code”, and “scripts” that the concept of habitus would have cleared up (see esp. pp. 3-6, 239-241). 7 For instance, one can combine habitus with an ecological conception of social structure or with a network-based vision of the social world, or yet mate it to an economistic vision of history. Whether this is the optimal move from a scientific standpoint is a different question from whether it is doable and desirable, and one that ultimately can be settled only empirically across a range of objets and over the long run. 6 More generally, Bourdieu‟s own proclivity to pilfer concepts from antagonistic theoretical strands and to selectively rework notions from paradigms he found flawed (neoKantian formalism and phenomenology, ordinary language philosophy and psychoanalysis, etc.) reveals his ingrained disregard for scholastic convention and his distaste for sanctifying readings of canonical authors. He was a tireless advocate of an epistemologically disciplined eclecticism when it comes to theory and we should adopt the same attitude toward his writings, rather than fall into the kind of “academicism” that he regularly excoriated. Paradis (2014: *) dutifully recites the established scholarly catechism, but the formula [(habitus) x (capital)] + field = practice that Bourdieu deliberately tucked away in a footnote of Distinction, so that it would not get noticed and reified into a magic recipe for social analysis, skates on the surface of his sociology. It is intended as a mnemotechnic device and not as an algebraic equation. Indeed, the conventional triad of “habitus, capital, field” that she invokes rather mechanically --but this is how Bourdieu is taught and used in a bookish mode-- is a simplified rendering of his framework. A deeper reading of Bourdieu‟s oeuvre suggests that it rests not on three but on six conceptual pillars (the triad plus doxa, symbolic power, and reflexivity), which can in turn be derived from the more fundamental duet of social space and symbolic power.8 Paradis‟s comment flags a prevalent danger: the reduction of Bourdieu‟s theory to what Kenneth Burke called “logology,” a play with words about words, if not a logomachy. Countless invocations of habitus (field, capital, doxa, etc.), which have proliferated at blinding speed in the wake of Bourdieu‟s academic canonization in the late 1990s, are merely rhetorical and play no part in the scientific construction of the object. Far too many authors are fluent “speakers of Bourdieuese” but routinely forget to effect the technical research operations that these concepts mandate; as a result, they carry out the same empirical analyses that they would without them. Or they erase the distinctiveness of Bourdieu‟s concepts by relying on secondary (tertiary, quarternary, etc.) interpretations that dull their analytical angles and turn them into bland synonyms for standard notions of the sociological vernacular.9 Thus, in her study of a women‟s full-contact boxing club in San Francisco, Paradis (2012) mistakes field for “social context” and confuses the pugilistic field proper --that is, the invisible web of positions occupied by agents competing for pugilistic authority and value-- with the concrete setting of the gym in which boxers ply their craft. She conflates the visible interactions between club members with the objective relations of power between the holders of the different forms of capital operative in pugilistic space (many of whom are just not present on the gym stage) so that, while the word “field” appears 76 times in her article, the concept is absent from her analysis. For the same reason, she confuses hysteresis, which is a constitutive property of every habitus referring to the built-in lag between the time it is forged and the moment it is activated (a temporal gap between cause and effect rooted in remanent embodiment) with an empirical “misalignment between habitus and doxa that makes agents feel out of place and out of sync” (Paradis 2012: 84). So much to stress that the mention of a concept in a text is not a guarantee that it exerts any effect in the inquiry. Yet for Bourdieu, as for his teachers in the philosophy of science Gaston Bachelard 8 Put crudely, capital and field are overlapping and partly redundant; social space is the root category of which field is but a historical-analytic specification; and at the epicenter of Bourdieu‟s lifework stands symbolic power, of which one manifestation is habitus. 9 This problem is especially salient for Bourdieu‟s concept of field, which has spawned numerous derivatives, knockoffs and ripoffs, from “organizational field” to “strategic action field” to “global field” and a string of related terms (world, game etc.). To equate field with an “arena of action” or patterned space of mutually focused activities animated by struggles or interests without further specification is to rob the concept of champ of its power (here is where keeping the original French term would have been helpful). 7 and Georges Canguilhem, concepts are not talismans but tools; not terms that close the discussion by dint of oratorial authority but practical pointers that guide and drive inquiry along definite empirical pathways. Paradise‟s (2014: *) second concern is that the differentiation of the cognitive, conative and emotive layers of habitus entail “an asocial socialization process” where “learning is multifaceted but solitary.” But a dispositional theory of action cannot by definition be solipsistic since it integrates (backward) and projects (forward) a sequence of common experiences based on social ties. As shown in Body and Soul for prizefighters, or by Lehmann (2002) for musicians in a symphony orchestra, Desmond (2007) for wildland firefighters, and Bourdieu (1984/1988 and 2013) himself for professors and painters, every component involved in the forging of habitus is quintessentially collective: the categories of perception are discerned and taught through joint activities; the skills are learned by observing and honed by acting in concert with members; the desires are aroused and channelled toward their proper objects in repeated interaction with other participants sharing the illusio specific to the universe studied. And the welding of the perceptual, kinematic, and cathectic components of habitus into a coherent working ensemble is also carried out collectively in practice through mimesis and osmosis. LIBIDO SCIENTIFICA The reactions of Downey (2014) and Mialet (2014) differ from those of Crossley and Paradise in that they both approach the question of embodiment and its uses as a research tool from alternative perspectives: the theory of culture and neuroanthropology for the former, Latour‟s actor-network theory and empirical philosophy for the latter. To respond fully would require a broader discussion of the merits and limitations of these two paradigms relative to Bourdieu‟s than can be offered here. So let me flag a few selected points of divergence and convergence. Like Crossley, Downey exaggerates the gap between Bourdieu‟s and my usage of habitus. He must do so to uphold the standard reading that has hardened over the years according to which, for Bourdieu, “habitus is uniform within a group, unchanging, and impervious to consciousness and explicit discussion” (Downey 2014: *). This view, reiterated in Downey‟s book Learning Capoiera and recent related publications (Downey 2005 and 2010), must be revised in light of the many texts in which Bourdieu documents the opposite. Recall that the French sociologist introduced the notion in his early studies of two disrupted sociohistorical junctures on the two sides of the Mediterranean:10 the destruction of the peasantry, forced mass migration, and emergence of an urban working class in late colonial Algeria; and the slow death of the village society correlative of the rise in bachelorhood in his home region of rural Béarn. On the Algerian side, Bourdieu tracks down and highlights how variations in peasant social structure and trajectory, linked to the depth and length of penetration by colonial authorities and monetary relations, translates into variations in subjective conceptions of time, labor, and value, i.e., variance in habitus that determine an opposition, within the same group, between “empeasanted peasants” and “dispeasanted peasants” as well as the emerging split between proletariat and subproletariat in the city. This split clearly shows that habitus evolve as they encounter new external conditionings and new social conditions of actualization --here Bourdieu (1977/1979: 96-114F) puts great stess on the role of housing (its stability, quality, location) as 10 See Wacquant (2004b) on the foundational status of these twinned cross-Mediterranean field studies and the entire special issue of Ethnography devoted to “Pierre Bourdieu in the Field” (voume 5, no. 4, December 2004) documenting their existential mixity and analytical unity. 8 determinant of the reorganization of the domestic economy and its articulation with the wageearning economy. Imperial domination also fosters the diffusion of hybrid habitus propelling splintered conducts, expectations, and aspirations, which create an opening for the deliberate shaping of consciousness by political action, to which Bourdieu sought to contribute through his research (Bourdieu and Sayad 1964/2005, Bourdieu 1977/1979, Bourdieu 2004).11 On the Béarn side, Bourdieu (2002/2008, originally 1963) finds that the breakdown of social reproduction in the rural community in which he grew up stems from the growing disjuncture between the habitus of the men and the habitus of the women of the same class and locality, due to their differential sensitivity to and capacity to master the cultural patterns issued from the city. In both of these foundational studies, then, Bourdieu stresses that habitus are --or, to be more precise, can be-- heterogeneous, changing, and open to symbolic manipulation --under historical conditions to be specified. And he returns to those themes at various junctures in his investigations into education, art, academic power, urban dispossession, gender inequality, and the state, whenever reality warrants. So what accounts for the staying power of the conventional view that stresses the opposite? I see two reasons for it. First, most scholars approach habitus in a theoreticist mode, reading Bourdieu‟s treatment of action through his more abstract and compact statements --in Outline of Theory of Practice for anthropologists, Distinction for sociologists, The Rules of Art for humanities scholars, and Reproduction for students of education-- instead of attending to what Bourdieu does with the notion in his extended and variegated empirical analyses. This leads to confounding the formal properties of the concept with their concrete manifestations in a given setting and case. Next, at the more abstract level, Bourdieu does stress the tendency of habitus to become stable, coherent, congruent with its operant milieu, and relatively resistant to conscious manipulation, and for good reason: there exist powerful mechanisms of selection, on the side of the agent as well as the side of the social world, that work to ensure the minimal coherence, congruence and persistence of dispositions (Wacquant 2014c). Briefly put, institutions weed out agents who do not adopt the requisite categories of perception, evaluation, and action; individuals drift away from settings that do not gratify their social libido and gravitate toward settings that do, where they congregate with others more likely to resemble them in their dispositional makeup and therefore reinforce their propensities. With this dissent, I have also registered one major point of agreement with Downey (2014: *): we must take habitus down to the empirical mat and strictly forbid wielding it as “a theoretical shield to artificially prevent an analytical tangling of materiality and subjectivity.” I concur with him that puzzling out the practical logics of action will require opening a dialogue with “emerging fields like cultural neuroscience” and related offshoots of biology. Bourdieu (1997/2000: 136) himself points us in that direction: in Pascalian Mediations, he notes that the acquisition of dispositions via learning entails “the selective and durable transformation of the body that operates via the strengthening or weakening of synapic connections.” At this point, he refers to the work of leading neurobiologist Jean-Pierre Changeux (2006), his colleague at the Collège de France, who later picked up that reasoning in an intriguing article on “The Neuronal Bases of Habitus.” 11 One quotation is enough to give a sense of how the colonial habitus comes to embody heterogeneity and instability on the cognitive, conative and affective planes: “In all realms of existence, at all levels of experience, one finds the same successive or simultaneous contradictions, the same ambiguities. The patterns of behavior and the economic ethos imported by colonization coexist inside of each subject with the patterns and ethos inherited from ancestral tradition. It follows that behaviors, attitudes, or opinions appear as fragments of an unknown language, as incomprehensible to someone who does not know the cultural language of the tradition as to someone who refers only to the cultural language of colonization” (Bourdieu and Sayad 1964/2004: 464). 9 But I would extend that collaboration further and center it on the variegated currents in cognitive science that have negotiated a sharp “turn to the body” over the past decade (see Wilson 2002, Shapiro 2007, Clark 2008, Noë 2009). The empirical work and theoretical arguments of scholars such as Francisco Varela, George Lakoff, Antonio Damasio, Andy Clark, Esther Thelen and Alva Noë are of direct and pressing import to students of habitus insofar as they are displacing the disincarnated philosophy of action that has ruled social inquiry since the Cartesian revolution and elaborating a monist model of the tangled dance of body, brain, self, and environment in practice (see Shapiro 2014 for an extended panorama).12 Let me note here, to reconnect with the tradition of historical rationalism, that this new “embodied cognitive science” and “enactive psychology” is effectively training its sights and technical tools back onto the agenda set out by Marcel Mauss (1974) in a series of papers given in the 1930s on the connections between psychology and sociology. It unpacks and turns into experimental puzzles Mauss‟s alluring sketch of “total man” as a “live gearing” of a body, an individual mind, and a collective conscience requiring the active collaboration of biology, psychology, and sociology.13 I am delighted that Hélène Mialet has joined this discussion because her provocative field study of the workaday production of a prize-winning producer of science, Hawking Incorporated (Mialet 2012), not only injects a live organism-in-action in a research genre where the body too often appears in the guise of just another text awaiting its lector. It reaches many of the same analytic conclusions that I do even as her object, research design, epistemological posture, and theoretical tools are in many ways diametrically opposed to mine. She followed a charismatic victor, Stephen Hawking, in a competitive mental endeavor that is culturally prestigious, socially valued, and materially sheltered; I toiled alongside no-name practitioners of a plebeian avocation pursued in dire penury and deservingly deemed to be the “red-light district of sport.” She proceeds from the ground up and from the scientist outward by tracing rings of exchanges along labile networks connecting the acting parties and their props; I start from the macrostructures of class inequality, racial subordination and masculine hubris, materialized by the hyperghetto, to delve into the web of social and material relations constitutive of the gym as secluded sociomoral forge, and then descend further down into the fleshly subjectivity of boxers. Our joint conclusions: social competency is embodied and tacit; knowledge accretes as a form of sensuous action in and upon the world; the body is the crucible that ongoingly welds passion and reason (as Damasio (2003) demonstrates from the side of neurobiology); membership rests on a bedrock of collective belief and embedded desire. But then we part at multiple junctures that I signpost with brief questions expressing my qualms about the mode of analysis hegemonic in today‟s Science and Technology Studies.14 12 Sociologists have already advanced with vigor on this front, as attested by Ignatow (2007), Lizardo (2009), Vaisey (2009), Cerulo (2010), and Martin (2011: chapters 3 and 4), and by the contributions to the symposium on my reworking of habitus published in Theory & Psychology (December 2009 and forthcoming). 13 If I diverge from Bourdieu, as Downey would wish me to, it is in the use of habitus as method: I am confident in the virtues of “observant participation” and sanguine about the promise of “armed apprenticeship” as a pathway to analytic knowledge of practical knowledge, whereas Bourdieu (2002) was rather skeptical of them. 14 This is not the place to address the problematic epistemic assumptions of Action-Network Theory. Suffice it to note that they are similar to those afflicting ethnomethodology, another hypersubjectivist paradigm that Latour (2005 : 12) and his associates seem keen on reinventing, as they dutifully “„follow the actors themselves‟, that is, try to catch up with their often wild innovations in order to learn from them what the collective existence has become in their hands” (a close paraphrasing of Harold Garfinkel‟s agenda, down the use of “methods” and “accounts” in the next sentence), as if those “actors” were omnipotent and omniscient and lived in a locally determined local world. 10 First, Mialet was an observer of the scene, and not a full-fledged participant in it: what additional layers of action did she miss by not diving into its brook? What roles could she have assumed on the scene (scribe, personal assistant, lab attendant, janitor) that would have gotten her closer to one of the manifold points of production of the master scientist and enabled her to shed the spectatorial viewpoint that sporadically resurges in her narration? Second, it appears that her “distributed-centered subject” (Mialet 2012: 9), the nodal carnal materialization of Latour‟s “actant,” can be recombined at a moment‟s notice and is in a state of perpetual flux, as if networks of persons, objects, and symbols had few hard boundaries, little structure, and no vectors of subordination --remarkably, the word power appears not once in her book. By contrast, habitus stipulates a clear initial analytic distinction between agent and world, so that we may study their empirical formation, encounter, and interpenetration; and it injects a strong sense of structure and domination at the epicenter of social analysis. It does so, and this is my third point of divergence, by avoiding the drift toward an instantaneist vision of action, where everything is determined here and now, and all the relevant factors are right at hand out in the open. As history made body, habitus not only introduces temporality; it also insists that the world is not transparent to social agents; that they have followed a trajectory and occupy a location in a resilient distribution of efficient resources independent of their will and consciousness. Whereas in the world of “actor-networks composed of humans and non-humans,” everything flows in an endless Brownian movement devoid of social gravity, opacity, and asymmetry, habitus begs for location in social time and social space --or in the series of nested microcosms pertinent to manufacturing the practice studied: in the case of Hawking, the scientific field inside the academic field inside the bureaucratic field inside the field of power (Bourdieu 2001/2004), all of which are beyond the analytic reach of actor-network theory. This is why, to flag one last difference, I am not “trapped by the classical definition of science,” as Mialet (2014: *) seems to worry; I am committed to it, wide awake, and fully aware of the promise, limitations, and even perversions of science as a historical endeavor and collective ideal. Ernst Cassirer (1944) shows, in his classic Essay on Man recapitulating twentyfive centuries of knowledge production, that science remains the most potent of all the symbolic systems yet invented by humans to make sense of their world and possibly shape it. I see no reason to throw out the baby of historical social science with the bathwater of positivism and to follow Latour in jettisoning the goal of social explanation for the mere description of associations --least of all under the specious motive that we would have entered a world where “things accelerate, innovations proliferate, and entities are multiplied” (Latour 2005: 12).15 I do subscribe to scientificity as a benchmark set by the joint deployment of reason and empirical observation, and so must every scholar in Science and Technology Studies who wishes that their work be read as something more than poetry. Does the aspiration to objectivity imply that a carnal social scientist “refuse[s] to be entirely affected, moved, or changed by the fieldwork she has undertaken” (Mialet 2014: *)? On the contrary, the very purpose of enactive ethnography is to submit oneself to the special social gravity and sensual magnetism of the phenomenon, precisely, to provoke those changes and use them as crucial data points recorded with one‟s own flesh and blood.16 The carnal sociologist 15 “What is called „social explanation‟ has become a counter-productive way to interrupt the movement of associations instead of resuming it” (Latour 2005: 8). 16 Here we rejoin with the concerns and teachings of George Devereux (1968) in From Anxiety to Method in the Behavioral Sciences, especially his recommendation to consider the disturbances caused by the overlap between subject and object as vital information and not as noise. 11 knows full well that she will not emerge the same at the other end of the experiment and she intuits that this coming self-transformation is not without risks and costs. But such is the wondrous potency of libido scientifica --for those who possess it or are possessed by it-- that she will throw herself body and soul into the work. REFERENCES Adkins, Lisa, and Beverley Skeggs (eds.). 2004. Feminism after Bourdieu. Oxford: Blackwell. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977/1979. Algeria 1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1979/1984. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1980/1990. The Logic of Practice. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1984/1988. Homo Academicus. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1987/1989. “Social space and symbolic power.” Sociological theory 7, no. 1 (Spring): 14-25. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1989/1998. The State Nobility: Elite Schools in the Field of Power. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1993/1999. “The Contradictions of Inheritance.” Pp. 507-513 in Pierre Bourdieu et al., The Weight of the World: Social Suffering in Contemporary Society. Cambridge: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1997/2000. Pascalian Meditations. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1998/2001. Masculine domination. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1999. “Le fonctionnement du champ intellectuel” (Lecture course of 8 November 1995). Regards sociologiques (Strasbourg) 17-18: 5-27. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1999/2008. “A conservative revolution in publishing.” Translation Studies 1, no. 2: 123-153. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2001/2004. Science of Science and Reflexivity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2002/2008. The Ball of Bachelors: The Crisis of the Peasant Society in Béarn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2002. “Participant Objectivation: The Huxley Medal Lecture.” Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 9, no. 2 (February): 281-294. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2004. “Algerian Landing.” Ethnography 5, no. 4 (Winter): 415-442. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2004/2008. Sketch for a Self-Analysis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2013. Manet. Une révolution symbolique. Paris: Seuil/Raisons d‟agir Éditions. Bourdieu, Pierre and Jacques Maître. 1994. “Préface dialoguée.” Pp. v-xxii in L’Autobiographie d’un paranoïaque. L’Abbé Berry (1878-1947) et le roman de Bill, Introïbo. Paris: Anthropos. Bourdieu, Pierre. 2008/2014. Algerian Sketches. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bourdieu, Pierre and Abdelmalek Sayad. 1964. Le Déracinement. La crise de l’agriculture traditionnelle en Algérie. Paris: Minuit. Bourdieu, Pierre and Abdelmalek Sayad 1964/2004. “Colonial Rule and Cultural Sabir.” Ethnography 5, no. 4 (Winter): 445-486. Cassirer, Ernst. 1944. An Essay on Man: An Introduction to a Philosophy of Human Culture. New Haven: Yale University Press. Cerulo, Karen A. 2010. “Mining the intersections of cognitive sociology and neuroscience.” Poetics 38, no. 2: 115-132. Changeux, Jean-Pierre. 2005. “Les bases neuronales de l‟habitus.” Pp. 143-158 in Gérard Fussman (ed.), Croyance, raison et déraison. Paris: Odile Jacob. Clark, Andy. 2008. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Coser, Lewis A. 1974. Greedy Institutions: Patterns of Undivided Commitment. New York: Free Press. 12 Crossley, Nick. 1996. Intersubjectivity: The Fabric of Social Becoming. London: Sage. Crossley, Nick. 2001a. The Social Body: Habit, Identity and Desire. London: Sage. Crossley, Nick. 2001b. “The phenomenological habitus and its construction.” Theory & Society 30, no. 1: 81-120. Crossley, Nick. 2006. Reflexive Embodiment in Contemporary Society: The Body in Late Modern Society. New York: McGraw-Hill. Crossley, Nick. 2013. “Habit and Habitus.” Body & Society 19, no. 2-3 (June & September): 136-161. Crossley, Nick. 2014. “Comment on Loïc Wacquant‟s Homines in Extremis.” Body & Society: in press (this issue). Damasio, Antonio. 2003. Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling Brain. New York: Mariner Books. Dalton, Benjamin. 2004. “Creativity, habit, and the social products of creative action: Revising Joas, incorporating Bourdieu.” Sociological Theory 22, no. 4: 603-622. Devereux, George. 1968. From Anxiety to Method in the Behavioral Sciences. The Hague: Mouton. Desmond, Matthew. 2007. On the Fireline: Living and Dying with Wildland Firefighters. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Downey, Greg. 2005. Learning Capoeira: Lessons in Cunning from an Afro-Brazilian Art. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Downey, Greg. 2010. “„Practice without theory‟: a neuroanthropological perspective on embodied learning.” Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 16, no. 1: 22-40. Downey, Greg. 2014. “Habitus in extremis: from embodied culture to bio-cultural development.” Body & Society: in press. Ignatow, Gabriel. 2007. “Theories of embodied knowledge: new directions for cultural and cognitive sociology?” Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 37, no. 2: 115-135. Hammoudi, Abdellah. 2007. “Phénoménologie et ethnographie: A propos de l‟habitus kabyle chez Pierre Bourdieu.” L’Homme 184: 47-83. Hancock, Black Hawk. 2013. American Allegory: Lindy Hop and the Racial Imagination. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. King, Anthony. 2000. “Thinking with Bourdieu against Bourdieu: A „practical‟critique of the habitus.” Sociological theory 18, no. 3: 417-433. Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the Social. New York: Oxford University Press. Lehmann, Bernard. 2002. L’Orchestre dans tous ses états. Ethnographie des formations symphoniques. Paris: Editions la Découverte. Lizardo, Omar. 2009. “Is a „special psychology‟ of practice possible? From values and attitudes to embodied dispositions.” Theory & psychology 19, no. 6 (2009): 713-727. Lordon, Frédéric. 2006. L’Intérêt souverain. Essai d’anthropologie économique spinoziste. Paris: La Découverte. Martin, John Levi. 2011. The Explanation of Social Action. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Mauss, Marcel. 1968. Œuvres. Vol. 2: eprésentations collectives et diversité des civilisation. Paris : Minuit. Mialet, Hélène. 2012. Hawking Incorporated: Stephen Hawking and the Anthropology of the Knowing Subject. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Mialet, Hélène. 2014. “The pugilist a nd the cosmologist: response to Wacquant‟s „Homines in extremis‟.” Body & Society: in press. Neveu, Érik. 2013. “Les sciences sociales doivent-elles accumuler les capitaux?” Revue française de science politique 63, no. 2: 337-358. Noë, Alva. 2009. Out of Our Heads: Why You Are Not Your Brain, and Other Lessons from the Biology of Consciousness. New York: Hill and Wang. Paradis, Elise. 2012. “Boxers, Briefs or Bras? Bodies, Gender and Change in the Boxing Gym.” Body & Society 18, no. 2 (June): 82-109. Paradis, Elise. 2014. “Sociology is a martial art.” Body & Society: in press. 13 Ritterhouse, Jennifer Lynn. 2006. Growing Up Jim Crow: How Black and White Southern Children Learned Race. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press. Sallaz, Jeffrey J. 2010. “Talking race, marketing culture: The racial habitus in and out of apartheid." Social Problems 57, no 2 (May): 294-314. Sewell, William H.. Jr. 1992. “A theory of structure: duality, agency, and transformation.” American Journal of Sociology 98, no. 1 (July): 1-29. Shapiro, Larry. 2007. “The embodied cognition research programme.” Philosophy compass 2, no. 2: 338346. Shapiro. Lawrence (ed.). 2014. The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition. London: Routledge Vaisey, Stephen. 2009. “Motivation and Justification: A Dual‐Process Model of Culture in Action.” American Journal of Sociology 114, no. 6 (May): 1675-1715. Wacquant, Loïc. 1993/1998. “Inside the Zone: The Social Art of the Hustler in the Black American Ghetto,” Theory, Culture & Society 15, no. 2 (May): 1-36. Wacquant, Loïc. 2002. “Scrutinizing the Street: Poverty, Morality, and the Pitfalls of Urban Ethnography.” American Journal of Sociology 107, no. 6 (May): 1468-1532. Wacquant, Loïc. 2004a. Body and Soul: Notebooks of an Apprentice Boxer. New York: Oxford University Press. Wacquant, Loïc. 2004b. “Following Pierre Bourdieu into the Field.” Ethnography 5. no. 4 (December): 387-414. Wacquant, Loïc. 2005. “Carnal Connections: On Embodiment, Membership, and Apprenticeship.” Qualitative Sociology, response to the Special issue on “Body and Soul,” 28, no. 4: 445-471. Wacquant, Loïc. 2013. “Symbolic Power and Group-Making: On Bourdieu‟s Reframing of Class.” Journal of Classical Sociology 13, no. 2 (May): 274-291. Wacquant, Loïc. 2014a. “Homines in extremis: What Fighting Scholars Teach us about Habitus.” Body & Society: in press. Wacquant, Loïc. 2014b. “Marginality, Ethnicity and Penality in the Neoliberal City: An Analytic Cartography.” Ethnic & Racial Studies Review, Symposium (with responses from Andy Clarno, Michael Dawson, Matt Desmond, Amy Lerman, Glenn Loury, Mara Loveman, Douglas Massey, Dorothy Roberts, Robert Sampson, William Julius Wilson, Andreas Wimmer): in press. Wacquant, Loïc. 2014c. “Habitus as Bridge between Sociology and Psychology.” Theory & Psychology, Symposium on habitus, forthcoming. Wilson, Margaret. 2002. “Six views of embodied cognition.” Psychological Bulletin & Review 9, no. 4 (December): 625-636. BIO: Loïc WACQUANT is professor of sociology at the University of California, Berkeley, and researcher at the Centre européen de sociologie et de science politique, Paris. His interests include urban marginality, penality, carnality, and social theory. His books have been translated in two dozen languages and include Body and Soul: Notebooks of An Apprentice Boxer (2004, new expanded edition, 2014), The Two Faces of the Ghetto (2014), and Tracking the Penal State (2014). For more information, see loicwacquant.net. * Forthcoming in Body & Society, response to the Symposium on “Homines in extremis,” Summer 2014